5 Dual-Purpose incentives: can pay destroy intrinsic motivation?

In Section 3 we discussed dual-purpose incentives as they arise in conventional models of extrinsic rewards, noting that they arise in many contexts, including the use of compensation practices to signal some otherwise-unobserved characteristic of the firm, to avoid adverse selection of workers along some otherwise-unobserved characteristic, and to deal with multi-tasking. We return in this section to the study of incentives that must do “double duty,” but now the second role concerns intrinsic motives.

5.1 Pay and selection on dedication

To set the stage, we begin with an extremely simple model in which increasing pay induces adverse selection along an important dimension—dedication to the job. Our case considers a group of workers who are qualified for a particular occupation that for many is a “calling” or “vocation.” There are many examples of this sort of dedication: religious ministry, policy advocacy, nursing, early childhood education, public-interest law, etc. The “calling” in this case is a potentially important form of intrinsic motivation. In this section we take a vocational inclination to be an unobserved feature of preferences. In subsequent sections, however, we allow for the possibility that the intensity of an agent’s “calling” might be reinforced or eroded by the behavior of the principal or peers.

Specifically, we consider the model set up by Heyes (2005) and analyzed further by one of us (Taylor, 2007). The analysis, which uses the market for nurses as the focus of discussion, begins with simple behavioral assumptions. There are image qualified nurses, each of whom falls into two categories: (i) A proportion of these nurses, image, view nursing as simply a job. These individuals receive utility equal to their wage, image, and they produce value image on the job. (ii) The remaining proportion, image, is comprised of nurses who view work as a “vocation.” They provide higher-quality nursing along an unobservable dimension, image. They also find their work fulfilling, and thus earn money metric utility image beyond the earned wage image.

Each individual has a reservation wage image which is drawn from a log concave p.d.f., image, that has a corresponding c.d.f., image. The function image is assumed to be the same for both types of worker. Thus, at wage image, the quantity of nursing labor supplied is


image     (35)


and the average quality is of nursing care is


image     (36)


where image is the proportion of employed nurses for whom nursing is a vocation, i.e.,


image     (37)


Heyes’ key insight is that this latter proportion is declining in the wage.52 Thus, the higher the wage, the lower will be the quality of services provided.

Consider an employer acting in isolation, e.g., a monopsonistic National Health Service (NHS), that hires nurses. (In different markets one could think of the Roman Catholic church setting wages for priests or nuns, or Habitat for Humanity setting wages for professional builders who take part-time positions constructing affordable housing.) Heyes shows that an employer who understands the adverse selection properties of high wages will set the wage to be lower than would otherwise be chosen. Thus, an NHS that maximizes surplus generated by nurses will operate with an apparent “shortage” of nursing, in the sense that the expected net value of product will be positive for the marginal nurse.

It is possible indeed that the principal will be driven to a corner solution, with pay set to zero. Thus, Habitat for Humanity has the well-known policy of using unpaid volunteers for many key tasks. Organization that seek to remedy injustice in the legal system often rely on pro bono attorney services. Historically, many religious workers take a “vow of poverty,” accepting compensation at near-subsistence levels. The idea, of course, is that the lower the pay, the higher will be the dedication level of individuals willing to adopt the vocation.

Taylor (2007) extends Heyes’ analysis to show that a monopsonist that seeks to maximize surplus generated by workers will always set the wage lower than the socially efficient level. The reason is that the monopsonist fails to take account of the surplus generated to those individuals who view their work as a vocation. Because wages are too low, too few vocationally-oriented workers end up in an occupation in which they create the greatest social value.

On the other hand, a parallel analysis in Taylor (2007) shows that if the labor market is perfectly competitive, the equilibrium wage will be inefficiently high. To see how this happens, notice that under the assumption that all workers must be paid the same wage, a social planner would want to maximize


image     (38)


where image is taken to be the value of the worker in some other capacity (with image being the highest value in the distribution). Maximization of (38) leads to the wage being set to be the weighted sum,


image     (39)


Next notice that in a competitive market the wage instead will equal average productivity,


image     (40)


Using the property of log concavity given in Footnote 52, we can compare wages in (39) and (40), finding that image. The problem with the competitive market is that each firm makes hiring decisions on the basis of average market productivity. A social planner would instead make decisions on the basis of the productivity of the marginal worker, i.e., would take account of the fact that as the wage increases in the market, the productivity of the marginal worker declines.

This simple model serves as a first illustration of an important point that reappears throughout this section of our essay: Pay policies can affect intrinsic motivation, often in surprising ways. Here, high pay reduces intrinsic motivation in a workforce in a particularly transparent way. Low-pay environments attract workers for whom the job is a vocation—workers who have an intrinsic inclination to provide high-quality service. The higher the pay, the greater will be the proportion of workers for whom the job is simply a job, i.e., workers who will provide lower-quality service.

A particularly interesting feature of this simple behavioral model is that markets can lead to wages being either too high or too low relative to an efficient benchmark, depending on the market’s structure. To see the logic of this point, consider this question: “If you were a falsely convicted death-row inmate, would you rather be in a State in which you must rely on an organization that reviews cases using pro bono attorney services, or in a State that purchases legal services on the competitive market?” In the State that relies on pro bono services, attorneys who work on death-penalty cases will be highly dedicated to justice, and will provide excellent legal aid, but that aid will be in short supply. In contrast, in a State that purchases legal services for death-row inmates, access to attorneys may be more extensive, but those attorneys will have a lower expected level of dedication. Our model shows that in the State that relies on pro bono attorneys, the wage is too low and the quality level too high relative to the efficient benchmark. But in the State that uses the competitive market, the wage is too high and the quality too low. Theory alone does not identify the socially preferred second-best outcome.

Recently, a number of papers have examined models in which agents differ in their level of intrinsic motivation. Delfgaauw and Dur (2007), for example, have a wage posting model in which a monopsonist faces the same tension discussed above: the higher the posted wage, the higher the probability of filling a vacancy, but the lower the expected motivation level of workers who apply. In their model, workers have private information about their utility—information which they may wish to signal to or conceal from an employer. Besley and Ghatak (2005) and Delfgaauw and Dur (2008) study public sector employment under the assumption that some agents have a “public service motivation” that takes the form of intrinsic value derived from making a contribution to one’s organization.53

The model we have examined in this section omits, obviously, several relevant issues that merit further consideration. For instance, the set-up abstracts from the core problem of agency; workers are simply assumed to supply effort on the basis of their internal intrinsic values. Second, workers are assumed to be steadfast; motivation is not affected by the actions of those around them. Thus, a worker who is inclined to provide high quality service is not de-motivated when she is surrounded by others who provide low quality service. In short, the analysis abstracts from “social preferences” of the sort discussed in Section 4. Third, the model does not take account of the possibility that a worker’s motivation can be affected by attributions the agent might place on the intentions of the principal. It is easy to see that such attributions might be germane, though, in the case of the “service motivations” we have been discussing.54 Finally, the set-up does not allow for the possibility that a worker’s intrinsic motivation (image in the model above) can be reinforced or undermined by pay policies. We turn next to models that take up such issues.

5.2 Social preferences, conformism, and the principal’s use of extrinsic rewards

Recent work by Sliwka (2007) considers the question of agency in a model that draws on a “social preference framework,” i.e., allows for agents’ motivation to be shaped in part on the behavior of those around them. As in the model set out in the last section, there is heterogeneity in worker motivation, and an agent’s motivational inclinations are initially hidden to the principal and to other agents. There are two types of “steadfast” agents. One type is “strictly selfish;” these are agents who care only about their own payoff. Agents of the second type are “fair” in the sense that they care about the wellbeing of others; specifically, for these agents, utility is increasing in the principal’s payoff. The key innovation is to assume that there is yet a third group, “conformists,” whose inclination toward fairness depends the values of those around them. To keep matters simple, Sliwka assumes that when a conformist learns what agent type is in the majority, the conformist behaves like the majority-type agent.

In this set-up, a principal who understands that most of his steadfast workers are fair, might be able to use compensation policies as a credible signal to “conformists.” In turn, if conformists believe that others around them are “fair” they behave like fair agents.

To see how this works, we set up a simple example similar to that developed by Sliwka. In our example, the principal first posts a policy that specifies wage as a function of effort (which is assumed to be observable ex post), image. An agent’s best response to the announced policy depends, of course, on his preferences over effort and money, and those preferences in turn vary by type. In particular,


image     (41)


where image reflects a fair agent’s level of identification with the principal’s objective (with image).

We assume that the principal sets compensation to have a fixed component and a “bonus” that is a linear function of effort, image. Given that types are unobserved, the principal’s posted wage-bonus policy applies to all agents. It is easy to see that for an announced compensation policy, best responses are


image     (42)


With this in mind, consider a profit-maximizing principal who earns surplus


image     (43)


for a given agent. Given the best responses in (42), it is clear that effort is increasing in the incentive intensity; image for both types of steadfast agent. Sufficiently high effort-contingent bonuses would seem to be in order.55 Remarkably, it might nonetheless be in the principal’s best interest instead to set image equal to 0 and increase the baseline wage, i.e., to rely solely on low-powered incentives.

The key is the emergence of a separating equilibrium in which conformists become convinced that most steadfast agents are fair. It is assumed that the firm has private information about the proportion of steadfast agents who belong to each type, which for simplicity is taken to have a low value or a high value. It is a matter of simple algebra to confirm that there are parameter values for which the following holds: If the firm has a low number of fair agents, it pays a high bonus, image, and a low wage. If the firm has a high number of fair agents, it pays no bonus, image, and a relatively higher wage, i.e., it uses low-powered incentives. Here low-powered incentives serve as a credible signal, so conformists follow suit and behave like fair agents. This makes sense, because a principal who has a high fraction of steadfast fair agents will incur a smaller loss than a principal with a low fraction of fair agents when it sets the bonus to 0. A willingness by the principal to raise the fixed wage further strengthens the signal. Conformists, in response to this credible signal, behave like fair agents. Profit for this firm is higher than if it used higher-powered incentives.

The operating logic of the model is like the Taylor-Ritter model discussed in Section 3.1, in which the firm uses compensation policy to signal hidden information about itself (i.e., the firm’s financial fitness). In that model, low-powered incentives signal relatively good financial fitness, which allows the firm increased profitability.56 Here, the principal’s hidden information is the mix of worker type. There is a cost to low-powered incentives, of course, as effort is set by all agents to be less than first-best. But the low-powered incentive persuades some workers—the “conformists”—to behave in an altruistic fashion, when they would otherwise have not.

Sliwka interprets his model as generating “trust as a signal of a social norm.” In Sliwka’s setting, the principal observes effort and can, if he chooses, condition rewards on effort. By setting no explicit incentives, the principal expresses trust in his workers. This trust directs a social norm. Some workers are more generous in their efforts than they would have been if they perceived a different norm.

The most intriguing possibility in the Sliwka’s model is that monetary incentives crowd out intrinsic motivation. If a firm moves from a “high trust” low-powered incentive scheme to a “low trust” high-powered incentive scheme, the firm shifts the norm and undermines the intrinsic portion of worker’s motivation (the “social component” in the utility of a worker who would otherwise behave as a “fair agent”). Sliwka develops his theory further by looking at employee self-selection into firms. Here again, low-powered incentives can serve to attract workers with high intrinsic motives (fair agents), which serves to reinforce the positive work norms that influence those who conform to others.

The key behavioral underpinning of the Sliwka model is the observation that many people seem to want to conform to those around them. As we have noted, there is considerable evidence about the key component of this story—that many people are influenced by norms. For example, some individuals feel bad about a particular action only in situations in which they think others would experience remorse for that same action.57 In previous sections of this paper, we cited empirical work supportive of the social forces that create norms, e.g., studies by Ichino and Maggi (2000), in which worker absenteeism in an Italian bank was affected by the absenteeism of those around them, and Mas and Moretti (2009), in which effort by supermarket checkout workers was affected by other similar workers in their sightline. Yet another study, by Bandiera et al. (2009), shows that the productivity of farm workers is affected by the productivity of friends on the job. Jackson and Bruegmann (2009) document peer learning for teachers, which might be read as providing additional evidence on conformity to norms. Of course, considerably more empirical work will be required to know if conformism plays a sufficiently strong role to generate in real-world organizations the crowding out of intrinsic motivation predicted by the Sliwka model.

5.3 Extrinsic incentives when agents value the principal’s esteem

Ellingsen and Johannesson (2008) present a model that, like Sliwka’s, relies on social preferences. Also, like Sliwka’s, their model opens up the possibility that extrinsic incentives can undermine valuable intrinsic motivations.

The key innovation in the Ellingsen-Johannesson model is the postulate that human motivation is often rooted in social esteem—the desire to be well regarded by others. In this conception, an agent reasons as follows: “I wish for others to hold a high opinion of me. While I cannot know with certainty what others think of me, I do have beliefs about what others think, and these beliefs about others’ opinions are an important source of pleasure or discomfort.” The identity of the audience that the agent wishes to impress plays a key role in this model, and the agent might well have multiple audiences. For example, a college professor might care about opinions of her students, her dean, other professors in her department, and/or colleagues in the profession more generally. She desires the respect of the intended audience(s), i.e., gains utility if she believes that others think highly of her.

Ellingsen and Johannesson focus on the case in which the relevant audience to an agent is the principal. 58 To simplify use of personal pronouns, we let the principal be male and the agent be female. In the model, then, the agent’s utility depends on the “respect” she earns from the principal, which is defined to be her beliefs about his beliefs about her.

A simple example shows how the desire to earn respect can affect an agent’s effort decisions.59 Suppose there are two types of agent, “talented” and “untalented,” and type is not initially observable to the principal. An agent hired by a principal is paid an agreed-upon wage image, and then chooses any effort level she likes, image. We suppose that her utility is the sum of three components: (1) compensation image, (2) the cost of effort, which is image for a talented worker and image for an untalented worker, with image, and (3) “respect” of the principal, which has value image, where image is a positive constant and image is the agent’s subjective probabilistic assessment of the principal’s belief that the agent is talented. In sum,


image     (44)


Now, given (44), an untalented agent is clearly better off supplying effort 0 than supplying effort greater than image, even if the higher effort level would “earn maximum respect” (i.e., would induce the principal to believe with probability 1 that the agent is talented). So we have a separating equilibrium satisfying the Intuitive Criterion if a talented agent supplies effort image, which is just high enough so that the untalented agent will decline to mimic.60

In this example, a talented agent provides positive effort. She is not motivated by her own material wellbeing, as she would be in a standard principal agent model. Nor is she motivated by an innate desire to see the principal’s wellbeing improve, as with the other-regarding preferences assumed in the Sliwka model (or other such models discussed in Section 4). She provides effort because by so doing she can be confident that the principal holds a high opinion of her. Put another way, she is motivated by social esteem—the desire to earn respect.

With this basic logic in place, we can set out the Ellingsen-Johannesson model of principal-agent interaction. The model is built around three components. First, agents and principals hold social preferences. They care about their own material wellbeing as well as well as the material wellbeing of others. Second, there is unobserved heterogeneity in the extent to which agents and principals value others’ wellbeing. In particular there are two types on people, who vary in the extent to which they are pro-social. Third, and most distinctively, both the agent and the principal are motivated by social esteem, so the agent cares about what the principal thinks about her, and the principal cares about what the agent thinks of him. Both want to be thought of as pro-social by the other. Moreover, the agent’s concern about the principal’s opinion is highest if she thinks highly of him, i.e., believes it is likely that he is highly pro-social. Similarly, the principal places greater weight on the agent’s opinion if he believes that she is highly pro-social.

With these assumptions in place, Ellingsen and Johannesson examine the equilibrium of a game in which the principal takes an initial action (e.g., makes a wage offer, or makes a decision about how much discretion to allow the agent in her work), and then the agent takes an action which affects both her material wellbeing and the principal’s wellbeing. As in the simpler example in the preceding paragraphs, there is a set of parameters on preferences and the distribution of types such that a separating equilibrium emerges that satisfies the Intuitive Criterion. In that equilibrium a pro-social principal can take a credible action that signals that he is pro-social, and, if she is sufficiently pro-social, the agent responds with an action that benefits the principal. The key driving behavioral force is that a pro-social agent wishes to be highly regarded by a pro-social principal. Having learned that the principal is pro-social, the agent takes a pro-social action herself as a means of securing the knowledge that the principal believes her to indeed be a pro-social individual.

Figure 2 provides a nice illustration of the behavior predicted in this model. The game presented is the two player sequential “trust game” of McCabe et al. (2003):

image

Figure 2 A principal agent game of trust.

In Case 1, the first player (the principal) can choose “not trust” (NT), which leads to payoffs (20, 20) for the principal and agent respectively, or “trust” (T), which accords discretion to the agent. If the principal plays T, the agent can reward the trust (R), giving payoffs (25, 25) or not (N), giving payoffs (15, 30). With conventional preferences, the subgame perfect equilibrium is clearly “not trust.” However, in the McCabe-Rigdon-Smith experiments, many principals chose T, and most agents responded by rewarding such trust by playing R.

In Case 2, the principal has no choice but to play T. In contrast to Case 1, here most agents responded by playing N. Thus, the intentionality of the principal’s trust appears to matter for the agent’s response.

The Ellingsen-Johannesson model provides a rationale for these observed outcomes in the trust game. Start with Case 1. There are parameters in the model such that two key conditions are met. First, the principal will play T only if he is sufficiently pro-social, i.e., only if he cares sufficiently about the wellbeing of the agent. Second, a pro-social agent, having received a credible signal that the principal is pro-social, cares sufficiently about the respect of the principal that she in turn takes the action R, confirming that she is pro-social.

In contrast, in Case 2 the principal has no opportunity to signal that he is pro-social. In turn, the agent cares less about his respect, and so she plays N.

Ellingsen and Johannesson (2008) show, using similar logic, that their model predicts behavior consistent with Falk and Kosfeld’s (2006) experimental evidence on the hidden “cost of control” in a principal agent game. In the Falk-Kosfeld game, agents are given an endowment of 120 and can transfer image to the principal, who in turn receives payoff image, thus resulting in payoffs image. The important twist is that in some conditions of the game, there is a first stage in which the principal can play “control” by imposing a minimum transfer (e.g., a transfer of 10) from the agent to the principal, or can choose instead to “trust.” Agents motivated solely by material gain would always play the minimum available image, and knowing this, the principal would always “control” to the maximum extent allowed. But, in fact, consistent with the Ellingsen-Johannesson set-up, many principals sent a signal of being pro-social themselves by choosing “trust” when they are allowed to do so, and in such cases many agents responded with larger values of image than if the principal had played “control.”

One nice way to see the distinctive contribution of the “esteem model” is to view it in the context of Akerlof’s (1982) concept of gift exchange. Recall that in Akerlof’s model (discussed above in Section 4.2), an agent’s best response to a sufficiently generous “gift” by the principal is to reciprocate by providing high effort. The agent’s motivation to do so is captured in a clear, but stripped down fashion—with a utility function in which the agent experiences disutility only when her effort level exceeds a psychologically determined threshold (the effort “norm”). Ellingsen and Johnnesson take an additional step, positing an explicitly specified behavioral mechanism (“esteem”) that drives this motivation. This approach, the authors show, allows them to predict gift exchange behavior. But there are two advantages to the Ellingsen-Johannesson model:

First, the model gives a clear way of understanding the role of a principal’s intentions in shaping agents’ responses. This is important, given experimental evidence (such as (Charness, 2004)) that intentionality is important to understanding gift exchange.

Second, the model provides a rigorous way of approaching an important and under-appreciated aspect of principal agent problems as they apply in the workplace—the delegation of decision rights. Essentially, the delegation of consequential actions to agents plays the role of a “gift” here, and provides the agent with the opportunity to earn the respect of the principal. In contrast, highly intrusive job design diminishes intrinsic motivation.

These ideas are potentially valuable for understanding otherwise-inexplicable practices within organizations. For example, charitable organizations like Habitat for Humanity often rely on volunteers who receive little or no pay, and then delegate key decisions to these same individuals. By providing low pay, we have suggested (in Section 5.1 above), the organization is less likely to attract opportunists. Then the “esteem model” shows the important advantages to relinquishing bureaucratic control. A second example is the widespread use of “psychological contracts” (Rousseau, 1995) in which contracting parties find it advantageous to leave many elements unspecified, relying instead on mutual goodwill.

Conversely, the esteem model indicates why high pay and clearly delineated direction might be required in other circumstances. This can happen when the desire for esteem leads agents to have intrinsic motivation that works at cross purposes to the principal. For example, very strong financial incentives might be required to induce a physician to cut costs if the physician values the esteem of her patients more than the esteem of her boss (e.g., the managed care organization she works for).61

5.4 Extrinsic rewards and reputation

The Ellingsen-Johannesson model we have just discussed is one of a number of recent papers that focus on the interaction of pro-social motivation and reputation or esteem. This literature starts with the observation that people undertake altruistic and reciprocal actions (in the workplace and elsewhere), but recognizes that such behavior is often difficult to rationalize solely by other-regrading preferences. The degree to which people undertake pro-social behavior often depends on the social context and economic environment, and is driven in part by the desire to be highly regarded by others.

An important contribution to this literature is the recent work of Bénabou and Tirole (2006). Among the remarkable insights of this paper is a clear demonstration that extrinsic rewards can undermine intrinsic motivation when people care about reputation.

Consider the following anecdote: One of us has a particularly personable colleague who was asked by the dean to accept a somewhat onerous task—advising masters students—that would have high value to his colleagues. In exchange, the dean offered a $2000 bonus. The professor replied that it was certainly not worth taking on the task for $2000, but that he would be willing to do the job for free!

To demonstrate how the Bénabou and Tirole approach explains the behavior of this public-spirited professor, we set up a simplified case of their more general model. We suppose that a principal asks agents to undertake a pro-social activity by providing effort image. The agent can decline, instead providing image. The agent’s effort choice is observable by all, including members of an audience whose opinion matters to the agent.62

The agent’s effort decision is assumed to affect his utility via four channels, which for simplicity are taken to be additive: (1) The agent is other-regarding, and so earns direct utility, image, from providing effort image; (2) he stands to earn a material reward in the form of a bonus of image, which provides utility image (where image is the marginal utility of money); (3) he faces an effort cost of image; and, most distinctively, (4) he stands to gain from the reputation-enhancing effect of his effort choice.

Central to the Bénabou-Tirole model are the following two assumptions, which drive development of “reputation.” First, people differ in the extent to which they have other-regarding inclinations, and in the extent to which they value money. So each individual’s set of preference parameters, image and image, is drawn from a known distribution.63 An agent’s preference type can be thought of as his or her “identity.” Second, reputation is taken to be other’s views of one’s own identity. This reputation is increasing in the degree to which one is seen as having concern for others (having a high value of image) and decreasing in the degree to which he is seen as materialistic (having a high value of image).64 Thus, reputation is taken to be image, where image and image are weights that reflect the degree of image-consciousness (and are taken to be common knowledge constants here).

To summarize,


image     (45)


So our agent provides effort if


image     (46)


The three terms on the left-hand side of (46) are, respectively, the agent’s intrinsic, extrinsic, and reputational motivations. Effort is provided when the sum of these motivations exceeds the cost of providing effort.

What makes matters interesting here is that the reputation the agent earns depends on the level of the bonus image chosen by the principal. To see this point, consider first the effort decision if the principal chooses image, so that motivation is strictly intrinsic and reputational. Then the agent provides effort only if his “concern for others” exceeds the cut-off image, where


image     (47)


Such highly pro-social identity types lie to the right of the vertical “No Bonus” line in Fig. 3. Notice that in this situation the agent’s audience can draw an informative inference about the agent’s image (i.e., can infer if the agent is in an other-regarding pool to the right of image or narcissistic pool to the left of image) simply by observing the effort level, but can learn nothing about his materialism image.

image

Figure 3 The effects of an extrinsic reward on the pool of agents providing effort.

Now suppose that the principal provides a bonus image. For the moment, ignore any impact on reputation. The bonus has no effect on an agent with image, of course, but for all other agents (those with image) the bonus is motivating. Agents now provide effort if they have an identity that lies to the right of the negatively sloped line marked “Positive Bonus image, Unadjusted for Reputation.” Absent reputational effects, an extrinsic reward expands the pool of agents providing effort.

However, this is not the end of the story. Inspection of Fig. 3 makes it is clear that the average level of image (concern for others) has declined in the pool of agents providing effort and also in the pool of agents not providing effort. It is similarly clear that the average level of image (greed) has risen for the pool of those providing effort and declined for the pool not providing effort. So the overall effect on reputation is ambiguous. The most interesting possibility is that the effect of the bonus is to drag down overall reputation for those providing effort. This is demotivating. In Fig. 3 this is illustrated by the parallel shift to the right in the sloped line dividing those who provide effort and those who do not, with image now giving the value of image that separates the two pools for individuals along the horizontal axis (i.e., for individuals with image). On net, effects of the bonus are two-fold: Some identity types—those in Area A of Fig. 3—switch behavior to providing effort. Others—those in Area B—are induced to switch from effort provision to not providing effort. Overall, an extrinsic reward can increase or decrease effort, depending on the distribution of identity types.

The public-spirited professor in our anecdote is apparently an individual with an identity of the sort represented by Area B. Such a person has a relatively high concern for others and a relatively low level of greed. By offering a bonus for the task, the dean deprived the professor of the opportunity to demonstrate his public spiritedness.

In short, in the Bénabou-Tirole model, extrinsic rewards can spoil the reputational value pro-social action, thereby crowding out intrinsic motivation. The logic of the model is one of “signal extraction.” People take pro-social actions in part to signal one’s own identity to others. Extrinsic rewards, even very small extrinsic rewards, can serve to increase the noise-to-signal ratio of such actions.65

One of the most interesting ideas in the Bénabou and Tirole model appears when the authors reinterpret the “reputational” terms in (46) to instead be the reinforcement of one’s own self image. The idea is described as follows:

When making a decisions affecting others’ welfare, an individual will often engage in a self-assessment: “How important is it for me to contribute to the public good? How much do I care about money? What are my real values?” Later on, however, this information may no longer be perfectly “accessible” in memory—in fact, there will often be strong incentives to recall it in a self-serving way. Actions, by contrast, are much easier to remember than their underlying motives, making it rational to define oneself partly through one’s past choices: “I am the kind of person who behaves in this way” (Bénabou and Tirole, 2006).

Thus, the public-spirited professor might have found the offer of a $2000 bonus to be demotivating even if his colleagues were unaware of the bonus. Accepting the task without pay, in this conception, served to reinforce his identity; the professor can look at himself in the mirror and argue convincingly, “I must be a pro-social person. Otherwise I wouldn’t have taken on this task with no pay.”66

The striking prediction that extrinsic rewards can crowd out desired behaviors does have empirical support. One widely cited example in economics is work by Gneezy and Rustichini (2000b) showing that the imposition of a monetary penalty for late child pick-up at a daycare center increased the likelihood of late pick-up. Bénabou and Tirole’s reputation/self-respect model strikes us as applicable here. When there was no explicit monetary penalty for on-time pick-up, parents were presumably motivated by genuine concern for daycare center workers and by a desire to project to others (or to oneself) character traits of responsibility or concern for others. The imposition of a monetary penalty of course increased the inclination for on-time pick-up among those parents with a materialistic orientation and a low level of concern for others. This very fact led parents more generally to no longer view on-time pick-up as a reliable signal of kind and responsible identity, and so reduced the strength of those motivating forces. Similar arguments apply to Gneezy and Rustichini’s (2000a) demonstration that extrinsic incentives reduced effort by school children collecting donations for a charitable organization.67

Evidence of a potentially important form of crowding out is also found also in Frey and Oberholzer-Gee’s (1997) analysis of public reaction to the siting of a nuclear waste facility in one’s community. Their paper indicates that the provision of substantial compensation to residents of a host community reduces willingness to accept such a facility. The reputation/self-respect model might speak to these results, but it is quite possible that mechanisms described in Bénabou and Tirole (2003) are more germane. In that paper the authors set up a problem in which a principal seeks to motivate an agent to take a desired action in an environment in which the principal has better information than does the agent about some crucial aspect of the task—for example, the cost the agent will incur if she undertakes the task, the personal satisfaction she will experience if the task is completed successfully, or the likelihood that the agent will indeed be successful at the task. In this setting, the offer of a substantial monetary reward for some action can signal “bad news” to the agent about one of the elements of the action. Thus, if residents of a potential host community are asked to site a nuclear waste facility and are offered substantial compensation for doing so, that compensation might be seen as “bad news” about the eventual consequences of the facility.

The two papers we highlight in this section of our paper, Bénabou and Tirole (2003, 2006), are but two of a number of recent contributions in behavioral economics that might form solid building blocks for a new generation of behavioral principal agency models.68 The challenge going forward is to place the psychological subtleties introduced in these new economic models into workable (and testable) theories of firm organization and labor markets. It is important to have carefully constructed, psychologically correct models in behavioral economics, but important also to work forward to understand the implications of these models for the allocation of resources in markets and in society broadly.69

5.5 A concluding puzzle

The economic approach to agency places a primary emphasis on the use of material incentives (pay, promotion, etc.) as devices to resolve principal agent problems. The economic literature offers a rich and varied set of evidence in support of the critical efficacy and importance of material incentives. The theoretical literature reinforces these empirical findings. There are many situations in which firms eschew high-powered incentives, but for the most part this is the result of incentives having a powerful effect on behaviors. It is possible, as we have seen, to construct models where extrinsic rewards undermine intrinsic motives, but these models appear largely as elaborations and qualifications of the fundamental message: well designed extrinsic rewards are crucial to the resolution of fundamental and ubiquitous agency problems.

Things are quite different in the field of psychology. Here there has accumulated a vast amount of evidence that extrinsic rewards actually undermine intrinsic motives.70 What explains the difference?

One important part of the explanation is a cross-disciplinary difference in the definition of intrinsic motives. Psychologists typically view as extrinsic any sort of action undertaken for instrumental reasons. Thus many of the pro-social and other regarding preferences we discuss in Sections 4 and 5 would be regarded as part of an extrinsic reward system in the psychology literature.71

Economics is concerned with the efficient use of society’s material resources. In societies characterized by specialization and a sophisticated division of labor, almost all economic activity involves some degree of instrumental motives. Thus by defining the notion of intrinsic rewards so narrowly, psychologist’s have restricted their attention to a very small subset of economically relevant behaviors.

The focus, as peculiar is it might appear from an economist’s perspective, makes perfectly good sense from the perspective of psychology. After all, psychology is concerned with understanding the reward structures that drive human behavior. Why then should psychology privilege economically relevant motives?

There is another important difference in the ways that psychology and economics analyze extrinsic and intrinsic motivation: the handling of autonomy. Deci, Ryan, and other psychologists argue that feelings of autonomy and competence are fundamental to human happiness. To the extent that they cause people to become accustomed to responding to rewards rather than their own intrinsic drive for self-realization, extrinsic rewards undermine a fundamental determinant of psychological wellbeing.72

Positive economics, in contrast, conceives of autonomy simply as a means for achieving some productive end. For example, in standard principal agent models, high levels of autonomy are warranted when an agent has better information than does the principal about the consequences of actions, and can be rewarded on the basis of the value created by selecting the best action from a choice set. Even in Ellingsen and Johannesson’s esteem model, autonomy awarded by the principal serves the instrumental purpose of allowing the agent to signal valuable information to the principal. Economists have only begun to explore the interesting and provocative possibility that autonomy has value in and of itself and that the use of targeted extrinsic rewards (in the psychological sense) undermines an individual’s feeling of autonomy and competence.73

6 Conclusions

Our purpose in writing this chapter is to assess the contribution of behavioral economic ideas to the study of agency in employment relationships. In Section 2 we introduce the basic logic of standard agency models and in Section 3 we discuss the complications that arise when incentives must serve “double duty” as is the case where firms have to worry about adverse selection or multi-tasking. In Section 4 we introduce the core behavioral idea of “other regarding preferences” and consider effects on agency relationships of various manifestations of these preferences—equity considerations, effort norms, norms of professional practice and identity. In Section 5 we return to the theme of double duty incentives, and consider the possibility that incentives have the two-fold effect of motivating desired behaviors while also reinforcing (or undermining) intrinsic motives.

The narrow focus of our paper has caused us to give short shrift to many important contributions that behavioral economics has made to our discipline. We say relatively little about such important behavioral economic topics as prospect theory, hyperbolic discounting, mental accounting, status-quo biases and default rules, cognitive dissonance, or bounded rationality. Perhaps more noteworthy than the behavioral issues we have left out of this essay are the standard methodological approaches that we have kept in. Our intention has been to remain theoretically grounded and methodologically conservative. In each section of the paper we represent purposive behavior by analyzing equilibrium behaviors that emerge when individual agents maximize a utility function subject to participation constraints and the constraints imposed by incentive and monitoring systems. Also, consistent with standard economic analysis, we are careful to consider the ways in which equilibrium outcomes are shaped by market competition and by the selection of agents into employment relationships.

Even with this deliberately conservative approach, we find that the introduction of behavioral features into agency models leads to novel and important results: Inequity aversion among agents leads to lower powered incentives than would otherwise be the case, but this effect can be undone in certain competitive environments. Effort norms and “gift exchange” can support high effort levels even when monitoring and incentives are problematic, but reliance on effort norms requires that principals be exquisitely attuned to the ways in which their actions influence employee morale. Professional norms can have the effect of protecting consumers from exploitation by professionals and this effect can be reinforced by properly designed incentives. The protective value of these norms can, however, be undermined by self-serving biases that distort the judgement of professionals in unconscious ways. Identity matters for the resolution of agency problems within employment relationships and can help explain important empirical anomalies in labor markets. High powered extrinsic incentives can have a corrosive effect on the motivation of employees, especially when the employees work in “mission driven” or “caring” organizations or when preferences or identity are endogenously shaped by the incentives to which employees are exposed.

The application of behavioral economics to agency in employment relationships is a relatively new area of research. It is worthwhile then to speculate on what might be especially promising areas for future research. We highlight four such areas:

First, given the pivotal importance of professional norms for well functioning markets in health care and financial services, we think it would be useful to investigate more thoroughly the behavioral foundations of conflicts of interest. Very little is known about the ways these conflicts shape the psychology of decision making, and having a clearer understanding of this issue may be quite important for designing efficient and effective regulatory policies.

Second, models of identity have a great deal of appeal, because families, schools, and firms appear to devote enormous resources to shaping and refining the identity of their participants. As currently specified, however, models of identity are so flexible that they may not generate falsifiable conclusions. A satisfactory understanding of the economics of identity will therefore require either a more structured modeling approach or, more likely, the accumulation of additional sociological and psychological data on the nature of identity so that the parameters of the models can be empirically constrained.

Third, much more needs to be learned about the relationship between public policy and income and effort norms. Are Levy and Temin, for example, correct in their assertion that changes in Federal government policy in the 1980’s shifted the tolerance for income inequality throughout the labor market? Are Akerlof, Dickens and Perry correct that the effectiveness of monetary policy is determined by the workings of reciprocity and gift exchange in the workplace? At present we do not have definitive answers to these questions.

Finally, although the theory is new and the evidence not yet conclusive, we are intrigued by the notion that extrinsic rewards can undermine intrinsic motives. In health care, corporate governance, education, and other important settings, standard models typically prescribe some sort of “pay for performance” for resolving agency issues. This prescription must be greatly modified if we can identify people and contexts where high powered financial incentives undermine employee motives to do the right thing.

Clearly, there is much more to discover about the behavioral economics of agency in employment relationships.

References

Daron Acemoglu, Michael Kremer, Atif Mian. Incentives in markets, firms, and governments. Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization. 2008;24(2):273-306.

George A. Akerlof. The economics of caste and of the rat race and other woeful tales. Quarterly Journal of Economics. 1976;90(4):599-617.

George A. Akerlof. Labor contracts as partial gift exchange. Quarterly Journal of Economics. 1982;97(4):543-569.

George A. Akerlof, William T. Dickens, George L. Perry. Near-rational wage and price setting and the long-run Phillips curve. Brookings Papers on Economic Activity. 2000;2000(1):1-44.

George A. Akerlof, Rachel Kranton. Economics and identity. Quarterly Journal of Economics. 2000;115(3):715-753.

George A. Akerlof, Rachel Kranton. Identity and the economics of organizations. Journal of Economic Perspectives. 2005;19(1):9-32.

George A. Akerlof, Janet L. Yellen. A near-rational model of the business cycle, with wage and price inertia. Quarterly Journal of Economics. 1985;100(5):823-838.

George A. Akerlof, Janet L. Yellen. The fair wage-effort hypothesis and unemployment. Quarterly Journal of Economics. 1990;105(2):255-283.

Franklin Allen, Douglas Gale. Measurement distortion and missing contingencies in optimal contracts. Economic Theory. 1992;2(1):1-26.

Magnus Allgulin, Tore Ellingsen. Monitoring and pay. Journal of Labor Economics. 2002;20(2 part 1):201-216.

James Andreoni, B. Douglas Bernheim. Social Image and the 50-50 norm: a theoretical and experimental analysis of audience effect. Econometrica. 2009;77(5):1607-1636.

Jennifer Arlen, W. Bentley MacLeod. Torts, expertise, and authority: liability of physicians and managed care organizations. RAND Journal of Economics. 2005;36(3):494-519.

Kenneth J. Arrow. What has economics to say about racial discrimination? Journal of Economic Perspectives. 1998;12(2):91-100.

David Austen-Smith, Roland G. FryerJr. An economic analysis of ‘acting white’. Quarterly Journal of Economics. 2005;120(2):551-583.

Jerry Avorn. Powerful Medicines: the Benefits, Risks and Costs of Prescription Drugs. New York: Alfred A. Knopf; 2004.

Linda Babcock, Sara Laschever. Women don’t ask: negotiation and the gender divide. Princeton, Oxford: Princeton University Press; 2003.

Linda Babcock, George Loewenstein. Explaining bargaining impasse: the role of self-serving biases. Journal of Economic Perspectives. 1997;11(1):109-126.

Linda Babcock, George Loewenstein, Samuel Issacharoff, Colin Camerer. Biased judgments of fairness in bargaining. American Economic Review. 1995;85(5):1337-1343.

Oriana Bandiera, Iwan Barankay, Imran Rasul. Social connections and incentives in the workplace: evidence from personnel data. Econometrica. 2009;77(July):1047-1094.

Lucian Bebchuk, Jesse M. Fried. Executive compensation as an agency problem. Journal of Economic Perspectives. 2003;17(3):71-92.

Lucian Bebchuk, Yaniv Grinstein. The growth of executive pay. Oxford Review of Economic Policy. 2005;21(2):283-303.

Gary, S. Becker. The Economics of Discrimination. Chicago: University of Chicago Press; 1957.

Gary S. Becker. A Treatise on the Family. NBER Books; 1981.

Daryl J. Bem. Self-perception theory. Leonard Berkowitz, editor. Advances in Experimental Social Psychology, Vol. 6. New York: Academic Press; 1972.

Roland Bénabou, Jean Tirole. Intrinsic and extrinsic motivation. Review of Economic Studies. 2003;70(3):489-520.

Roland Bénabou, Jean Tirole. Incentives and prosocial behavior. American Economic Review. 2006;96(5):1652-1678.

Matthias Benz, Bruno S. Frey. Being independent is a great thing: subjective evaluations of self-employment and hierarchy. Economica. 2008;75:362-383.

Eli Berman. Sect, subsidy, and sacrifice: an economist’s view of ultra-orthodox jews. Quarterly Journal of Economics. 2000;115(3):905-953.

B. Douglas Bernheim. A theory of conformity. Journal of Political Economy. 1994;102(5):841-877.

B. Douglas Bernheim, Sergei Severinov. Bequests as signals: an explanation for the equal division puzzle. Journal of Political Economy. 2003;111(4):733-764.

Marianne Bertrand, Sendhil Mullainathan. Are CEOS rewarded for luck? The ones without principals are. Quarterly Journal of Economics. 2001;116(3):901-932.

Timothy Besley, Maitreesh Ghatak. Competition and incentives with motivated agents. American Economic Review. 2005;95(3):616-636.

Truman F. Bewley. Why wages don’t fall during a recession. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press; 1999.

Truman F. Bewley. Comments and discussion. Brookings Papers on Economic Activity. 2000;2000(1):45-50.

Alberto Bisin, Thierry Verdier. ‘Beyond the melting pot’: cultural transmission, marriage, and the evolution of ethnic and religious traits. Quarterly Journal of Economics. 2000;115(3):955-988.

Dan A. Black, Gary Gates, Seth Sanders, Lowell J. Taylor. Demographics of the gay and lesbian population in the United States: evidence from available systematic evidence. Demography. 2000;37(2):139-154.

Dan A. Black, Seth Sanders, Lowell J. Taylor. The economics of lesbian and gay families. Journal of Economic Perspectives. 2007;21(2):53-70.

Hannah Riley Bowles, Linda Babcock, Lei Lai. Social incentives for gender differences in the propensity to initiate negotiations: sometimes it does hurt to ask. Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes. 2006;103(1):84-103.

Hannah Riley Bowles, Linda Babcock, Kathleen L. McGinn. Constraints and triggers: situational mechanics of gender in negotiation. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology. 2005;89(6):951-965.

Samuel Bowles. The production process in a competitive economy: Walrasian, Neo-Hobbesian, and Marxian models. American Economic Review. 1985;75(1):16-36.

Samuel Bowles, Herbert Gintis. Schooling in Capitalist America: educational Reform and the Contradictions of Economic Life. New York: Basic Books; 1977.

Samuel Bowles, Herbert Gintis, Melissa Osborne. The determinants of earnings: a behavioral approach. Journal of Economic Literature. 2001;39(4):1137-1176.

Charles Brown, James Medoff. The employer size-wage effect. Journal of Political Economy. 1989;97(5):1027-1059.

Jeremy I. Bulow, Lawrence H. Summers. A theory of dual labor markets with application to industrial policy, discrimination, and Keynesian unemployment. Journal of Labor Economics. 1986;4(3):376-414.

Kenneth Burdett, Dale T. Mortensen. Wage differentials, employer size, and unemployment. International Economic Review. 1998;39(2):257-273.

Daylian M. Cain, George Loewenstein, Don A. Moore. The dirt on coming clean: perverse effects of disclosing conflicts of interest. Journal of Legal Studies. 2005;34(1):1-25.

Colin Camerer, Linda Babcock, George Loewenstein, Richard Thaler. Labor supply of New York City cabdrivers: one day at a time. Quarterly Journal of Economics. 1997;112(2):407-441.

Colin Camerer, George Loewenstein. Behavioral economics: past, present, future. In: Colin Camerer, George Loewenstein, Matthew Rabin, editors. Advances in Behavioral Economics. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2004.

Peter Cappelli, Keith Chauvin. An interplant test of the efficiency wage hypothesis. Quarterly Journal of Economics. 1991;106(3):769-787.

Randall Cebul, James Rebitzer, Lowell Taylor, Mark Votruba. Organizational fragmentation in the US health care system. Journal of Economic Perspectives. 22(4), 2008.

Gary Charness. Attribution and reciprocity in an experimental labor market. Journal of Labor Economics. 2004;22(3):665-688.

Gary Charness, Peter Kuhn. Lab labor: what can labor economists learn from the lab?. Developments in Research Methods and their Application. Orley Ashenfelter, David E. Card, editors. Handbook of Labor Economics. vol. 4a. 2011:229-330. (Chapter 3)

Gary Charness, Matthew Rabin. Understanding social preferences with simple tests. Quarterly Journal of Economics. 2002;117(3):817-869.

In-Koo Cho, David M. Kreps. Signaling games and stable equilibria. Quarterly Journal of Economics. 1987;102(2):179-221.

Ronald H. Coase. The nature of the firm. Economica. 1937;4(16):386-405.

David J. Cooper, James B. Rebitzer. Managed care and physician incentives: the effects of competition on the cost and quality of care. B.E. Journals in Economic Analysis and Policy: Contributions to Economic Analysis and Policy. 2006;5(1):1-30.

Bradford Cornell, Ivo Welch. Culture, information, and screening discrimination. Journal of Political Economy. 1996;104(3):542-571.

Pascal Courty, Gerald Marschke. An empirical investigation of gaming responses to explicit performance incentives. Journal of Labor Economics. 2004;22(1):23-56.

Jason Dana, George Loewenstein. A social science perspective on gifts to physicians from industry. Journal of the American Medical Association. 2003;290(2):252-255.

Edward L. Deci, Richard Koestner, Richard M. Ryan. A meta-analytic review of experiments examining the effects of extrinsic rewards on intrinsic motivation. Psychological Bulletin. 1999;125(6):627-668.

Edward L. Deci, Richard M. Ryan. Intrinsic motivation and self-determination in human behavior. New York: Plenum Press; 1985.

Josse Delfgaauw, Robert Dur. Signaling and screening of worker motivation. Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization. 2007;62:605-624.

Josse Delfgaauw, Robert Dur. Incentives and workers’ motivation in the public sector. Economic Journal. 2008;118:171-191.

Stefano DellaVigna. Psychology and economics: evidence from the field. Journal of Economic Literature. 2009;47(2):315-372.

Dominique J.F. deQuervain, et al. The neural basis of altruistic punishment. Science. 2004;305(5688):1254-1258.

Robert Dur, Amihai Glazer. The desire for impact. Journal of Economic Psychology. 2008;29(3):285-300.

Paul Ekman. Telling lies: Clues to Deceit in the Marketplace, Politics, and Marriage, 3rd ed. New York City: W. W. Norton and Company; 2001.

Tore Ellingsen, Magnus Johannesson. Paying respect. Journal of Economic Perspective. 2007;21(4):135-149.

Tore Ellingsen, Magnus Johannesson. Pride and prejudice: the human side of incentive theory. American Economic Review. 2008;98(3):990-1008.

William E. EncinosaIII, Martin Gaynor, James B. Rebitzer. The sociology of groups and the economics of incentives: theory and evidence on compensation systems. Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization. 2007;62(2):187-214.

Armin Falk, Ernst Fehr, Christian Zehnder. Fairness perceptions and reservation wages—the behavioral effects of minimum wage laws. Quarterly Journal of Economics. 2006;121(4):1347-1381.

Armin Falk, Andrea Ichino. Clean Evidence on Peer Effects. Journal of Labor Economics. 2006;24(1):39-57.

Armin Falk, Michael Kosfeld. The hidden costs of control. American Economic Review. 2006;96(5):1611-1630.

Henry S. Farber. Is tomorrow another day? The labor supply of New York City cabdrivers. Journal of Political Economy. 2005;113(1):46-82.

Henry S. Farber. Reference-dependent preferences and labor supply: the case of New York City taxi drivers. American Economic Review. 2008;98(3):1069-1082.

Ernst Fehr, Simon Gaecher. Cooperation and punishment in public goods experiments. American Economic Review. 90(4), 2000.

Ernst Fehr, Klaus M. Schmidt. A theory of fairness, competition, and cooperation. Quarterly Journal of Economics. 1999;114(3):817-868.

Ernst Fehr, Lorenz Goette. Do workers work more if wages are high? Evidence from a randomized field experiment. American Economic Review. 2007;97(1):298-317.

Ernst Fehr, Georg Kirchsteiger, Aron Riedl. Gift exchange and reciprocity in competitive experimental markets. European Economic Review. 1998;42(1):1-34.

Raquel Fernandez, Alessandra Fogli, Claudia Olivetti. Mothers and sons: preference formation and female labor force dynamics. Quarterly Journal of Economics. 2004;119(4):1249-1299.

Leon Festinger, James Carlsmith. Cognitive consequences of force compliance. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology. 1959;58(2):203-210.

Uris Fischbacher, Christina M. Fong, Ernst Fehr. Fairness, errors and the power of competition. Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization. 2009;72(1):527-545.

Fischer, Huddart. Optimal contracting with endogenous social norms. American Economic Review. 2008;98(4):1459-1475.

Raymond Fisman, Edward Miguel. Corruption, norms, and legal enforcement: evidence from diplomatic parking tickets. Journal of Political Economy. 2007;115(6):1020-1048.

Robert H. Frank. Are workers paid their marginal products? American Economic Review. 1984;74(4):549-571.

Robert H. Frank. Choosing the Right Pond: Human Behavior and the Quest for Status. New York: Oxford University Press; 1985.

Robert H. Frank. Passions within reason: the strategic role of the emotions. New York City: W. W. Norton and Company; 1988.

Bruno S. Frey. Not Just for The Money: An Economic Theory of Personal Motivation. Cheltenham: Edward Elgar; 1997.

Bruno S. Frey, Reto Jegen. Motivation crowding theory. Journal of Economic Surveys. 2001;15(5):589-611.

Bruno S. Frey, Felix Oberholzer-Gee. The cost of price incentives: an empirical analysis of motivation crowding-out. American Economic Review. 1997;87(4):746-755.

George-Levi Gayle, Robert A. Miller. Has moral hazard become a more important factor in managerial compensation? American Economic Review. 2009;99(5):1740-1769.

Martin Gaynor, James Rebitzer, Lowell J. Taylor. Physician incentives in health maintenance organizations. Journal of Political Economy. 112(4), 2004.

David Genesove, Christopher Mayer. Loss aversion and seller behavior: evidence from the housing market. Quarterly Journal of Economics. 2001;116(4):1233-1260.

Robert Gibbons. Incentives in organizations. Journal of Economic Perspectives. 1998;12(4):115-132.

Robert Gibbons, Michael Waldman. A theory of wage and promotion dynamics inside firms. Quarterly Journal of Economics. 1999;114(4):1321-1358.

Gicheva, Dora, 2009. Working Long Hours and Career Wage Growth. Working Paper, Yale University

Herbert Gintis, Samuel Bowles, Robert Boyd, Ernst Fehr. Explaining altruistic behavior in humans. Evolution and Human Behavior. 2003;24(3):153-172.

Uri Gneezy, Niederle Muriel, Rustichini Aldo. Performance in competitive environments: gender differences. Quarterly Journal of Economics. 2003;118(3):1049-1074.

Uri Gneezy, Aldo Rustichini. A fine is a price. Journal of Legal Studies. 2000;29(1):1-17.

Uri Gneezy, Aldo Rustichini. Pay enough or don’t pay at all. Quarterly Journal of Economics. 2000;115(3):791-810.

Jeffrey Grogger. Welfare reform, returns to experience, and wages: using reservation wages to account for sample selection biases. Review of Economics and Statistics. 2009;91(3):490-502.

Sanford J. Grossman, Oliver D. Hart. The costs and benefits of ownership: a theory of vertical and lateral integration. Journal of Political Economy. 1986;94(4):691-719.

Theodore Groves, Yongmiao Hong, John McMillan, Barry Naughton. Autonomy and incentives in Chinese state enterprises. Quarterly Journal of Economics. 1994;109(1):183-209.

Theodore Groves, Yongmiao Hong, John McMillan, Barry Naughton. China’s evolving managerial labor market. Journal of Political Economy. 1995;103(4):873-892.

Brian Hall, Thomas Knox. Underwater options and the dynamics of executive pay-to-performance sensitivities. Journal of Accounting Research. 2004;42(2):365-412.

Brian Hall, Jeffrey Liebman. Are CEOS really paid like bureaucrats? Quarterly Journal of Economics. 1998;113(3):653-691.

Brian J. Hall, Kevin J. Murphy. The trouble with stock options. The Journal of Economic Perspectives. 2003;17(3):49-70.

Randall Heron, Erik Lie. What fraction of stock option grants to top executives have been backdated or manipulated? Management Science. 2009;55(4):513-525.

Anthony Heyes. The economics of vocation or why is a badly paid nurse a good nurse? Journal of Health Economics. 2005;24:561-569.

Bengt Holmström. Moral hazard and observability. Bell Journal of Economics. 1979;10(1):74-91.

Bengt Holmström. Managerial incentive problems: a dynamic perspective. Review of Economic Studies. 1999;66(1):169-182.

Bengt Holmström, Paul Milgrom. Multitask principal-agent analyses: incentive contracts, asset ownership, and job design. Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization. 1991;7:24-52. Special Issue (Papers from the Conference on the New Science of Organization)

Bengt Holmström, Paul Milgrom. The firm as an incentive system. American Economic Review. 1994;84(4):972-991.

Hornstein, Andreas, Krusell, Per, Violante, Giovanni, 2007. Frictional wage dispersion in search models: a quantitative assessment. NBER Working Paper

Andrea Ichino, Giovanni Maggi. Work Environment and individual background: explaining regional shirking differentials in a large Italian firm. Quarterly Journal of Economics. 2000;115(3):1057-1090.

Howell E. Jackson. The trilateral dilemma in financial regulation. In: Anna Maria Lusardi, editor. Improving the Effectiveness of Financial Education and Savings Programs. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2008.

Jackson, Kirabo C., Bruegmann, Elias, 2009. Teaching students and teaching each other: the importance of peer learning for teachers. Manuscript

Brian A. Jacob. Accountability, incentives and behavior: the impact of high-stakes testing in the Chicago public schools. Journal of Public Economics Volume. 2005;89(5–6):761-796.

Brian A. Jacob, Steven D. Levitt. Rotten apples: an investigation of the prevalence and predictors of teacher cheating. Quarterly Journal of Economics. 2003;118(3):843-877.

Michael Jensen, Kevin J. Murphy. Performance pay and top-management incentives. Journal of Political Economy. 1990;98:225-264.

Lawrence M. Kahn, Peter D. Sherer. Contingent pay and managerial performance. Industrial and Labor Relations Review. 43(3), 1990. 107S-120S

Eugene Kandel, Edward P. Lazear. Peer pressure and partnerships. Journal of Political Economy. 1992;100(4):801-817.

Marc Knez, Duncan Simester. Firm-wide incentives and mutual monitoring at continental airlines. Journal of Labor Economics. 2001;19(4):743-772.

Alan B. Krueger, Alexandre Mas. Strikes, scabs, and tread separations: labor strife and the production of defective Bridgestone/Firestone tires. Journal of Political Economy. 2004;112(2):253-289.

Alan B. Krueger, Lawrence H. Summers. Efficiency wages and the inter-industry wage structure. Econometrica. 1988;56(2):259-293.

Renee Landers, James Rebitzer, Lowell J. Taylor. Rat race redux: adverse selection in the determination of work hours in law firms. American Economic Review. 86(3), 1996.

Renee Landers, James Rebitzer, Lowell J. Taylor. Work norms in professional labor markets. In: Francine Blau, Ronald Ehrenberg, editors. Gender and Family Issues in the Workplace. New York: Russell Sage Press, 1997.

Kevin Lang. A language theory of discrimination. Quarterly Journal of Economics. 1986;101:363-382.

Edward P. Lazear. Pay equality and industrial politics. Journal of Political Economy. 1989;97(3):561-580.

Edward P. Lazear. Personnel economics for managers. New York: John Wiley and Sons; 1998.

Edward P. Lazear. Culture and language. Journal of Political Economics. 107(6, part 2), 1999. S95–S126

Edward P. Lazear. Performance pay and productivity. American Economic Review. 2000;90(5):1346-1361.

Mark R. Lepper, David Greene, Richard Nisbett. Undermining children’s intrinsic interest with extrinsic reward: a test of the ‘overjustification’ hypothesis. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology. 1973;28(1):129-137.

David I. Levine. Just-cause employment policies in the presence of worker adverse selection. Journal of Labor Economics. 1991;9(3):294-305.

Levy, Frank, Temin, Peter, 2007. Inequality and Institutions in 20th Century America. NBER Working Paper

W. Bentley MacLeod, James Malcomson. Implicit contracts, incentive compatibility, and involuntary unemployment. Econometrica. 1989;57:447-480.

James M. Malcomson. Work incentives, hierarchy, and internal labor markets. Journal of Political Economy. 1984;92(3):486-507.

James M. Malcomson. Individual employment contracts. Orley Ashenfelter, David Card, editors. Handbook of Labor Economics, vol. 3 (number 3). 1999.

Alexandre Mas. Pay, reference points, and police performance. Quarterly Journal of Economics. 2006;121(3):783-821.

Alexandre Mas. Labour unrest and the quality of production: evidence from the construction equipment resale market. Review of Economic Studies. 2008;75(1):229-258.

Alexandre Mas, Enrico Moretti. Peers at work. American Economic Review. 2009;99(1):112-145.

Kevin A. McCabe, Mary L. Rigdon, Vernon L. Smith. Positive reciprocity and intentions in trust games. Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization. 2003;52(2):267-275.

John McMillan, John Whalley, Lijing Zhu. The impact of China’s economic reforms on agricultural productivity growth. Journal of Political Economy. 1989;97(4):781-807.

Don A. Moore, George Lowenstein. Self-interest, automaticity, and the psychology of conflict of interest. Social Justice Research. 2004;17(2):189-202.

Daniel Nagin, James Rebitzer, Seth Sanders, Lowell Taylor. Monitoring and motivation: an analysis of a field experiment. American Economic Review. 92(4), 2002.

Derek Neal. Why has black-white convergence stopped? In: Eric Hanushek, Finis Welch., editors. Handbook of the Economics of Education, vol. 1. Amsterdam: Elsevier, 2006.

Muriel Niederle, Lise Vesterlund. Do women shy away from competition? Do men compete too much? Quarterly Journal of Economics. 2007;122(3):1067-1101.

Paul Oyer. The Fiscal year ends and nonlinear incentive contracts: the effect on business seasonality. Quarterly Journal of Economics. 1998;113(1):14985.

Paul Oyer, Scott Shaefer. Personnel economics: hiring and incentives. New Developments and Research on Labor Markets. Orley Ashenfelter, David E. Card, editors. Handbook of Labor Economics. vol. 4b. 2011:1769-1823. (Chapter 20)

Canice Prendergast. The provision of incentives in firms. Journal of Economic Literature. 1999;37(1):7-63.

Canice Prendergast. The motivation and bias of bureaucrats. American Economic Review. 2007;97(1):180-196.

Canice Prendergast, Robert H. Topel. Favoritism in organizations. Journal of Political Economy. 1996;104(5):958-978.

Matthew Rabin. Incorporating fairness into game theory and economics. American Economic Review. 1993;83:1281-1302.

Matthew Rabin, Richard H. Thaler. Anomalies: risk aversion. Journal of Economic Perspectives. 2001;15(1):13.

James B. Rebitzer. Job safety and contract workers in the petrochemical industry. Industrial Relations. 1995;34(1):40-57.

James B. Rebitzer, Lowell J. Taylor. A model of dual labor markets when product demand is uncertain. Quarterly Journal of Economics. 1991;106(4):1373-1383.

James B. Rebitzer, Lowell J. Taylor. Efficiency wages and employment rents: the employer size wage effect in the job market for lawyers. Journal of Labor Economics. 1995;13(4):678-708.

James B. Rebitzer, Lowell J. Taylor. The consequences of minimum wage laws: some new theoretical ideas. Journal of Public Economics. 1995;56(2):245-255.

Joseph A. Ritter, Lowell J. Taylor. Workers as creditors: efficiency wages and performance bonds. American Economic Review. 1994;84(3):694-704.

Ritter, Joseph A., Taylor, Lowell J., Racial Disparity in Unemployment. Review of Economics and Statistics (forthcoming)

Denise M. Rousseau. Psychological Contracts in Organizations: Understanding Written and Unwritten Agreements. Thousand Oaks: Sage Publications; 1995.

P. Rudman, L.A. Glick. Feminized management and backlash toward agentic women: the hidden costs to women of a kinder, gentler image of middle managers. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology. 1999;77(5):1004-1010.

Richard M. Ryan, Edward L. Deci. Intrinsic and extrinsic motivations: classic definitions and new directions. Contemporary Education Psychology. 2000;25(1):54-67.

David Sally. Two economic applications of sympathy. Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization. 2002;18(2):455-487.

Carl Shapiro, Joseph Stiglitz. Involuntary unemployment as a worker discipline device. American Economic Review. 1984;74(3):433-444.

Herbert A. Simon. A formal theory of the employment relationship. Econometrica. 1951;19(3):293-305.

Dirk Sliwka. Trust as a signal of a social norm and the hidden costs of incentive schemes. American Economic Review. 2007;97(3):999-1012.

Deborah Small, Michele Gelfand, Linda Babcock, Hilary Gettman. Who goes to the bargaining table? The influence of gender and framing on the initiation of negotiation. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology. 2007;93(4):600-613.

Kathryn E. Spier. Incomplete contracts and signalling. RAND Journal of Economics. 1992;23(3):432-443.

Betsy Stevenson, Justin Wolfers. Economic growth and subjective well-being: reassessing the Easterlin paradox. Brookings Papers on Economic Activity. 2008.

Lowell J. Taylor. Optimal wages in the market for nurses: an analysis based on Heyes’ model. Journal of Health Economics. 2007;26(5):1027-1030.

Richard H. Thaler, Cass R. Sunstein. Nudge: Improving Decisions About Health, Wealth, and Happiness. Yale University Press; 2008.

Oliver E. Williamson. The Economic Institutions of Capitalism. New York: Free Press; 1985.

Kathleen L. Valley, Joseph Moag, Max H. Bazerman. ‘A matter of trust:’ Effects of communication on the efficiency and distribution of outcomes. Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization. 1998;34(2):211-238.

1 For the moment we take the cut-off as given, but as will become apparent, in this particular model it is important that the chosen cut-off be lower than the hoped-for level of performance, image.

2 The second order condition is image, which is satisfied if image exceeds the cut-off image. Hence our observation in the previous footnote that image must be below the hoped-for level of effort.

3 Natural alternative conceptions would allow for risk aversion, as in the Holmström’s (1979) classic paper.

4 In particular, they estimate that during the period 1980-1994 a typical CEO whose actions caused the firm to move from the 30th percentile of annual returns to the 70th percentile enjoyed an increase in annual compensation of 1 to 4 million dollars (1994 dollars), mostly through the increased value of the CEO’s stocks and stock options. For stellar performance the increase in CEO wealth was estimated to be much higher.

5 Concavity is natural here. The assumption image simply allows for the fact that some expenditures on CEO wellbeing are efficient.

6 We prove this latter result formally in Section 2.2.3 for the important case in which there is an ongoing (multiple period) relationship between the principal (firm) and agent (CEO).

7 Notice that this result holds even though we assume that agents are risk neutral. The result is reinforced, of course, if the agent is risk averse.

8 Hall and Knox (2004) estimate that at the height of the bull market in 1999, roughly a third of executive options were under water. Companies often respond to this non-linearity in stock option returns by increasing option grants following stock price declines.

9 This last assumption follows naturally enough, given the utility function we have specified. In our discussion of behavioral models in Section 4, we allow for the possibility that workers do care directly about the effort or compensation of other workers.

10 It is important here that the manager actually follows through on the promise to award the higher wage to workers who have the highest realized values of image. This might be sensible, especially if realized values of image are reasonably well known by people within the firm. After all, why wouldn’t the manager want to reward to workers who have the highest performance outcomes? Having said that, if there is “favoritism” based on other criteria, the proposed incentive plan falls apart. For more on favoritism see Prendergast and Topel (1996).

11 This wage solves a two-period participation constraint. The first period wage is low, possibly negative.

12 In Malcomson’s (1984) set-up, the agency problem is left unresolved for older workers. The point is that young workers can be motivated by the promise of future prizes (promotions, raises, etc.). Such incentives are less likely to be effective for workers nearing retirement. This is quite typical in agency-based models of “internal labor markets,” and it doesn’t substantially alter the basic insights generated in these models.

13 There are now a number of insightful overviews of the topic, including Lazear (1998), Prendergast (1999), Malcomson (1999), Gibbons (1998), and Oyer and Shaefer’s chapter in this Handbook.

14 See, e.g., McMillan et al. (1989), Groves et al. (1994) and Groves et al. (1995).

15 Similar points were also made in the important work of Bowles (1985). For additional theoretical development, see MacLeod and Malcomson (1989).

16 Valuable long-term employment relationships are central to these models, and thus so are shocks to employment. The model here can be enriched to allow for these exogenous shocks to employment relationships, but for simplicity we omit this feature.

17 This shows that efficiency wage motivation can lead to socially optimal effort levels, but this need not always be the case. For example, Allgulin and Ellingsen (2002) show that there can be distortions away from the socially optimal effort level when the principal has discretion over investments in monitoring.

18 In fact, the probability of retention is shown to be image.

19 Note that the rate image is a known constant to any individual, but of course is endogenous to the economy as a whole. We solve for the equilibrium rate image shortly.

20 Hornstein et al. (2007) offer a review and discussion of models of unemployment resulting from search frictions. Search models produce both unemployment and wage dispersion, but search frictions sufficient to account for equilibrium unemployment imply far less wage inequality than is actually observed.

21 In this model, young workers have concerns about the realization of high earnings at the firm later in their careers. Wages paid to young workers thus depend on the degree to which firms are judged to be unstable.

22 In the law firm context, the term of art for paying very high wages to summer interns and associates is “paying full freight.” Law firms that are able and willing to “pay full freight” signal that the value of their partnership is high, and this in turn allows them to attract the best talent.

23 Intuitively, the over-work equilibrium might persist even when there is a small number of low-effort workers. No one firm can deviate from the equilibrium without suffering harm from adverse selection. But if all firms backed away from overwork requirements, any one firm would get stuck with only a negligible number of low-effort workers. All firms would be better off.

24 A number of papers have taken up this issue, including Lazear (1989).

25 Maximize image subject to image.

26 From a legal perspective, employees are distinguished from independent contractors by the extent of control and supervision the principal exerts over the actions of the agent. A large literature focuses on the forces that drive firm boundaries, focusing on such issues as the direction of employee activities (e.g., Coase, 1937 and Simon, 1951), and firm ownership of assets (e.g., Williamson, 1985; Grossman and Hart, 1986). The relationship between these issues, and the agency problem—particularly in the multi-tasking setting—is developed clearly in Holmström and Milgrom (1994).
Many papers examine the relationship between firm boundaries and employment relationships in specific industry settings. See, as examples, Arlen and MacLeod’s (2005) analysis of physicians in managed care organizations, and the research one of us conducted on worker contracts in the petrochemical industry (Rebitzer, 1995).

27 For example, several decades back Gary Becker initiated important strands of inquiry in economics by positing preferences that incorporate such factors as “altruism” (Becker, 1981) or “distaste” for interaction with people of a different race (Becker, 1957).

28 Assessments based on reference points play an important role in behavioral economics generally, included features germane to labor economics. Kahneman and Tversky’s “prospect theory” of decision making under uncertainty argues that individuals are loss averse and that they calculate gains and losses relative to (potentially manipulable) reference points (Rabin and Thaler, 2001). Sometimes reference points are determined by the status quo or by inertia (e.g., Thaler and Sunstein, 2008; Genesove and Mayer, 2001).
We do not discuss labor supply here, but note that reference points can be important in those models as well. Camerer et al. (1997), for instance, argue that the labor supply of taxi drivers seems to entail drivers evaluating their daily income relative to a daily target. (See also Farber (2005, 2008) for additional evidence, some of it to the contrary, and DellaVigna (2009), for a clarifying discussion.) Fehr and Goette (2007) provide evidence for a field experiment suggesting that loss aversion and reference points may be important in determining work intensity.

29 Camerer and Loewenstein (2004) provide a nice justification for this approach: “Theories in behavioral economics image strive for generality—e.g., by adding only one or two parameters to standard models. Particular parameter values then often reduce the behavioral model to the standard one, and the behavioral model can be pitted against the standard model by estimating parameter values. Once parameter values are pinned down, the behavioral model can be applied just as widely as the standard one.”
More generally, Camerer and Lowenstein’s paper provides an insightful introduction to a broad and rich set of ideas in behavioral economics, including observations about the origins of modern behavioral economics, and suggestions about future directions for the field. DellaVigna (2009) gives a good recent review of behavioral economics, focusing on evidence drawn from the field.

30 This is the basis, for example, of the well-known “Easterlin paradox”—the paradoxical results that (i) individuals who are low in a nation’s income distribution report themselves to be unhappy, (ii) the average level of unhappiness does not much vary across nations with different levels of aggregate income, and (iii) countries do not get much happier as they get richer. While there is evidence to suggest that absolute income matters for happiness (e.g., Stevenson and Wolfers, 2008), it seems clear that one’s standing on the economic totem pole matters as well. Frank’s (1985) well known book provides an interesting and wide-ranging discussion on the human inclination for social comparison.

31 The assertion that utility is influenced by inequality aversion represents a “stripped down” way of characterizing the behavioral phenomena under study. Our initial treatment makes no distinction about agent attributions concerning the nature of inequality (e.g., what the inequality might say about the principal’s intentions or other agents’ intentions). We consider more sophisticated approaches below.

32 That paper also provides reference to a large relevant experimental literature.

33 These attitude questions were collected in an anonymous survey of employees conducted before the field study began.

34 This idea is modeled in an insightful way in an important paper by Rabin (1993). Charness and Rabin (2002) provide a clear statement of the ideas, and give reference to further literature. They also give compelling evidence from laboratory experiments on reciprocity. For a discussion of additional experimental evidence, see the chapter by Charness and Kuhn in this Handbook.

35 In a population entirely composed of cooperators there will be little reason to devote resources to monitoring the actions of others. This is an environment in which opportunists will thrive. Conversely, in an environment with many opportunists, cooperators will enjoy an advantage so long as they devote resources to monitoring their counterparts. Evolutionarily stable equilibria will therefore involve a mix of opportunists and cooperators with the latter spending resources seeking to weed out or punish the former. See, e.g., Gintis et al. (2003).

36 The fact that some individuals will punish opportunists even when it is not in their direct material interest suggests that punishment is supported by psychological reward mechanisms rather than rational calculation. Consistent with this view, recent brain imaging studies taken during an economic experiment involving trust and retaliation suggest that punishment of individuals who violate trust activates a brain region, the Caudate, that is involved in actions motivated by anticipated rewards (deQuervain et al., 2004). High Caudate activation likely reflects the anticipated satisfaction from punishing defectors.

37 On net, Falk and Ichino estimate a positive impact on output due to these peer effects similar to estimates of peer effects on absenteeism behavior found in Ichino and Maggi’s (2000) study of workers in different branches of a large Italian bank.

38 A nice exception is Knez and Simester (2001). This case study of Continental Airlines finds evidence of the apparent success a firm-wide incentive scheme that paid out a modest sum of money to almost all employees if the airline’s aggregate on-time departure statistics cleared a certain threshold. The authors argue that effort norms, enforced by the relatively small and homogeneous ramp and ground crews at each airport, could and did augment the low-powered financial incentives inherent in the bonus plan.
An important question concerns the extent to which norms can persist in cross-functional work groups where the social distance between members of the group might be high. Such work groups—composed of employees with widely different levels of income, status and education—play an important role in the health care system (e.g., in teams that include surgeons and high school educated technicians working together to improve processes). The failure of effort norms and peer pressure to operate in these settings likely contributes to inefficiencies in our health care system (as described, e.g., in Cebul et al. (2008), and other papers referenced therein).

39 See also Bewley’s (2000) comments on the paper, in which he argues that internal wage comparisons within the firm’s wage structure can be a key force in shaping macroeconomic outcomes.

40 Indeed, the outcome is potentially efficient.

41 For evidence that judgements of professionals (and others) can be shaped by unconscious but self-serving biases, see Babcock et al. (1995) and Babcock and Loewenstein (1997) and references therein.

42 Another largely neglected theme in the economics of professional norms is whether these norms are strengthened or weakened by market competition. Cooper and Rebitzer (2006) argue that competition between HMOs for patients and providers actually magnifies the importance of physician practice norms, and limits the willingness of managed care organizations to control costs via incentive contracts.

43 For example, practices at West Point are designed to “inculcate non-economic motives in the cadets so that they have the same goals as the US Army” (Akerlof and Kranton, 2005), and firm or workgroup loyalty can be found more generally in many organizations.

44 Babcock and Laschever (2003) provide an engaging and wide-ranging discussion. The authors present real-world evidence about women’s general disinclination to ask, and they include observations about the implications for gender inequality.

45 The point here is that individuals are not passive carriers of their social identities and, as Akerlof and Kranton note, there are many instances in which identities are supported by sometimes severe social sanctions meted out to those whose behavior deviates from proscribed behaviors.

46 For example, as Bulow and Summers (1986) note, if women generally have lower labor market attachment than men (perhaps because they are more likely to withdraw from the market for bearing and raising children or elder care), efficiency wages will be less effective in motivating women than in motivating men. This leads to an equilibrium in which a higher proportion of women than men will end up in the “secondary sector.” As a second example, long-hours work norms that emerge in rat race models, such as those of Landers et al. (1996) might be particularly disadvantageous to women. See Landers et al. (1997) for a discussion of this latter issue.

47 In this essay we focus on the effect of gender identity on agency problems, but gender identity is also likely to be very important for understanding female labor supply. In an intriguing and ingenious study, Fernandez et al. (2004), find that married women are more likely to work outside of the home if they are married to a man whose mother worked outside the home. A causal link is established by the use IV estimation, with cross-State variation in male World War II mobilization rates as the instrument.

48 In the broad social sphere, Bisin and Verdier’s (2000) analysis of ethnic identity and intermarriage makes a strong prediction that if families value homogamous matches (matches between men and women in the same ethnic group), minority families will make greater investments in identity-preserving activities than majority families, because there is a greater chance that their children will enter heterogamous matches. In a field study of one workplace, Bandiera et al. (2009) document workplace favoritism based on nationality (presumably because of social connections between those who share language and national origin) that is costly to the firm. As for sexual orientation, it seems possible that when gay individuals take the (possibly very costly) break from powerful expectations to adopt a heterosexual identity and norm, this reduces costs for deviation from traditional norms along other dimensions, such as occupational choice. Along these lines, Black et al. (2000) show that during the Korean War era (1950-1954), military service rates were 12 times higher for lesbian women than other women, and Black et al. (2007) show that lesbian college graduates sort into traditionally male majors at substantially higher rates than other women. We know of no work in economics that explores implications for organizations and labor markets.

49 See also the excellent discussions by Cornell and Welch (1996) and Lazear (1999). The idea that minority individuals might be more difficult to assess than non-minority workers is of course also at the root of the classic work on statistical discrimination. (See, e.g., Arrow, 1998, for references to earlier literature, and a thoughtful discussion.) Austen-Smith and Fryer (2005) provide an additional important perspective.

50 Grogger (2009) provides another piece of evidence consistent with the idea that impediments to black-white interactions spill over into the labor market. Even when he controls for skill and family background, blacks with speech patterns that sound distinctively black (according to anonymous listeners) are found to be relatively less successful in the labor market.

Even so, the miscommunication story we have outlined is likely a modest part of the profound racial divide in the US, as indicated by the black-white gap in unemployment and labor force participation, as well as many other economic and social dimensions.

51 Similarly, Ritter and Taylor (forthcoming) use the Rotter measure as a control in one of their unemployment regressions, finding that men with high internal control (measured when they are young) have lower subsequent unemployment. (The same is not true of women, though.)

52 To see that point, take the derivative of image with respect to image. The derivative has the same sign as image, which is negative for a log concave function.

53 See also Prendergast (2007), who sets out a model in which there is variation in the degree to which agents care about the outcome of some action they might take, as when bureaucrats vary in the extent to which they have altruism and empathy for individuals they are serving. One example he develops concerns social workers hired to determine eligibility for public assistance programs. While a “client-serving ethic” is important for this occupation generally, that same trait may be an impediment for the bureaucratic task at hand.

54 For example, when an organization hires motivated agents to pursue some jointly-shared social goal, agents must believe that they indeed are advancing that goal. Presumably, religiously-oriented individuals will be demoralized if they discover that are working for a corrupt church. See, e.g., Besley and Ghatak (2005) for a discussion along these lines.

55 With perfect information, the bonus would be image for a selfish agent and image for a fair agent. Ideally, the principal prefers a larger bonus for a selfish agent, but will want to have a positive bonus for fair agents as well as long as image. Notice also that fair agents have “intrinsic motives;” they provide effort even when the bonus is 0.

56 Similar logic pertains in Spier’s (1992) model, in which a principal knows more about the profitability and riskiness of a project than does an agent, and in Allen and Gale (1992), in which a supplier has superior information about his ability to distort a signal of production costs.

57 There is a great deal of empirical work across disciplines on norms. One particularly evocative story is told by Fisman and Miguel (2007): When United Nations diplomats in New York were given immunity for parking violations, violations were much higher among diplomats from countries that have high levels of corruption than from countries that have low levels of corruption. This suggests a powerful role for cultural norms. At a theoretical level, work by Bernheim (1994) is important. Fischer and Huddart (2008) discusses the role of endogenous social norms on organizational design.

58 Kandel and Lazear’s (1992) important work on peer pressure, in contrast, focuses on the case in which an agent values the regard of co-workers.

59 The example set out here follows Ellingsen and Johannesson (2007).

60 For such an equilibrium to exist, we need for the difference between image and image to be large enough to support separate actions by the two types. Suppose it is common knowledge that proportion image of agents are talented. If all agents were to supply image, agents would earn respect image. But in such a proposed equilibrium, it would be worth it to a maverick talented agent to play image, and thereby earn respect image, only if image, which boils down to image.

61 Quite possibly, carefully constructed models of esteem formation can make predictions about the interaction between organizational design and society’s class structure. Esteem motives, after all, break down if the principal is not a member of the audience, i.e., the class of individuals whose respect the agent values. Thus, if female identity is formed in a way that leads women to especially value the esteem of men, male bosses would have a distinct advantage over female bosses when supervising women. Bosses in high positions in racial hierarchies, ethnic hierarchies, or other socially determined hierarchies would be similarly advantaged.

62 To simplify matters, suppose that the agent is already in the principal’s employ and is now being asked to undertake a task that was not originally part of the job (as in the example of the public-spirited professor). It would be a worthwhile task to apply the Bénabou-Tirole model in a labor market generally (which would require attention to participation constraints, and to the way in which an announced compensation policy might affect selection into a firm).

63 To keep things simple here, we suppose that the parameters are independent.

64 Concern for others (“kindness”) and moderation in materialistic pursuit (“temperance”) are but two of the seven virtues. By leaving the other five virtues unstudied, perhaps Bénabou and Tirole signal “patience” (leaving them for future work) and “humility” (deference to other behavioral economists who wish to study those virtues).

65 Indeed, in more general versions of their model, Bénabou and Tirole show that extrinsic rewards can reverse the sign of the signal! Armed with this logic, the authors establish interesting and surprising insights around the use of such non-monetary motivators as praise and shame. They show, for example, that the excessive use of praise can backfire if pro-social behavior “becomes suspected of being motivated by appearances.” They also study the equilibrium development of social norms.

66 Bénabou and Tirole (2006) note that the key idea—“that individuals take their actions as diagnostic of their preferences”—is found in psychology in Bem’s (1972) self-perception theory and is related to the Festinger and Carlsmith’s (1959) theory of cognitive dissonance.

67 Frey and Jegen (2001) provide further reference to the literature, and discuss crowding effects from an economic perspective. See also Frey (1997).

68 Among the many other potentially relevant examples are the models of social image in Bernheim and Severinov (2003) and Andreoni and Bernheim (2009). The Bernheim-Severinov model is designed to explain the common practice of equal division of bequests. The model posits that children care about the extent to which they are loved relative to other siblings, and then studies bequests as a mechanism by which parents can signal love. Equilibrium behavior tends to pool at equal bequest division. Similar logic might explain the frequent organizational practice of equality in treatment (pay, work conditions, etc.) of workers who might differ quite widely in productivity. Andreoni and Bernheim’s refinement of these ideas might serve as a valuable microfoundation for studying the role of fairness (e.g., Fehr and Schmidt, 1999) in principal agent relationships.

69 The beautiful work of Akerlof and his co-authors—in papers on the economic implications of reciprocal motives, cognitive dissonance, social distance and identity—provides a template in this regard.

70 Important theoretical constructs include Lepper et al.’s (1973) overjustification theory and Deci and Ryan’s (1985) self-determination theory. A large number of carefully constructed experiments provide evidence favoring these theories, including many that demonstrate crowding out of intrinsic motivation (e.g., Deci et al., 1999).

71 For instance, in Ryan and Deci’s (2000) taxonomy, intrinsic motivation is reserved for “the doing of an activity for its inherent satisfactions rather than for some separable consequences.” Extrinsic motivation, on the other hand, “pertains whenever an activity is done in order to attain some separable outcome.” Such extrinsic motivation includes “external regulation” with a material reward or punishment, but also includes “introjection,” which focuses on approval from others or from oneself, and also, remarkably, “integrated regulation,” which occurs when an agent comes to assimilate the external driver as an internal driver. To quote Ryan and Deci (2000), “The more one internalizes the reasons for an action and assimilates them to the self, the more one’s extrinsically motivated actions become self-determined. Integrated forms of motivation share many qualities with intrinsic motivation, being both autonomous and unconflicted. However, they are still extrinsic because behavior motivated by integrated regulation is done for its presumed instrumental value with respect to some outcome that is separate from the behavior, even though it is volitional and valued by the self.”

72 Deci and Ryan’s theory of self-determination, for example, emphasizes the innate psychological needs for a sense of competence and autonomy. The authors suggest that “interpersonal events and structures (e.g., rewards, communications, feedback) that conduce toward feelings of competence during action can enhance intrinsic motivation for that action because they allow satisfaction of the basic psychological need for competence. Accordingly, for example, optimal challenges, effectance promoting feedback, and freedom from demeaning evaluations are all predicted to facilitate intrinsic motivation” (Ryan and Deci, 2000).

73 See, e.g., Benz and Frey’s (2008) research on the value of independence and Dur and Glazer’s (2008) work on the desire by workers for impact.

We are grateful for very helpful comments from Linda Babcock.

..................Content has been hidden....................

You can't read the all page of ebook, please click here login for view all page.
Reset
3.138.123.106