4
KNOWLEDGE MANAGEMENT’S THEORIES*

4.1 FINDING SOME NEW DIRECTIONS

What has been uncovered so far is a highly complex landscape, not least in the diversity of opinion over the nature of knowledge itself. This single issue is shown to impact on most if not all of the other debates in knowledge management (KM): for instance, the definition of KM, ethical issues associated with the management of knowledge, the commodification and reification of knowledge, reportedly high failure rates, the question of how to measure knowledge outcomes, whether knowledge is personal or organizational, or both, and cultural specificity. In considering two of the most prominent themes in KM besides that over the definition of knowledge—knowledge creating and sharing—we find that the diversity of perspective on the former lies behind the variety of claims in respect of influencing and impacting factors in both of these themes. All of these issues, it has been suggested, have potential consequences for research and practice. If the definition of knowledge is the subject of such considerable debate, what of KM’s theories?

It seems that KM finds its origins in many different disciplines, which might imply a broad theoretical spectrum. We can see early evidence of this in an ambitious survey of 160 KM frameworks by the researcher Peter Heisig (see also Sections 1.2 and 2.6). He uses a statistical content analysis method to identify how these frameworks approach three issues: how knowledge is understood, knowledge management activities, and identification of critical success factors in KM. Of particular interest, top success factors are categorized as “human orientated” (e.g., culture, people, and leadership), “organization,” and “technology,” which has resonance with mainstream thinking. References to context, environment, and learning are found to be absent. This absence, as the directions of this and subsequent chapters illuminate, is significant. Still, the finding of a broad consensus on the importance of human factors in KM success is encouraging, if a little obvious. Knowledge would not “exist” without people nor would organizations for that matter. This is nonetheless one of the few studies that attempts to rationalize the theoretical landscape.

Writing in 2001, Thomas Grover and his colleague predicted that KM would melt into the fabric of the organization becoming part of the daily operations and strategies. Do KM’s theories steer its practice along this course? This chapter investigates some of the most influential and popular theories (and some which should have been), showing how one in particular has dominated for more than two decades despite its alleged flaws and misrepresentations. Theories are classified according to a novel taxonomy of theory to better enable the comparing and contrasting of various paradigms: classification criteria are “knowledge as social action” versus “knowledge as object” and a focus on the “organizational level of analysis” versus a focus on the “personal level”. It draws on a critical review of almost 50 theories and frameworks. In particular, the taxonomy illuminates what could be seen as a growing trend toward a view of knowledge as accomplished in social action and bound to context. “Context” has been identified in the previous chapter as one of the four categories of knowledge sharing (KS).

The practical aims and objectives of the following discussions are (i) to provide managers and organizational leaders in particular with a “ready-reckoner” to assist in the identification of theories of interest and compatibility with their own organizational strategies and (ii) to offer a compass of theory to rationalize both navigation and analysis. The overall ambition is to investigate and analyze KM theory with the aim of identifying trends, themes, and gaps, which can, in turn, be used to determine potential new directions for the field of KM.

The discussions begin with a brief discussion around what constitutes a theory to set some preparatory groundwork. The main investigations and discussions are initiated with an introduction and explanation of the taxonomy of KM theory. Using this as a framework, we are able to compare and contrast theories classified at various points on the taxonomy’s axes, highlighting those of particular interest and relevance. An entire section is devoted to what is described as the most influential and popular of all KM theories, The Dynamic Theory of Organizational Knowledge Creation and its various developments. In particular, the investigations address the principle ways in which this theory is criticized.

This chapter’s penultimate section briefly discusses what is meant by inductionism, explaining how, from these perspectives, the most influential KM theory, and indeed many others, may be questioned on matters of validity, for instance. The chapter concludes with four primary conclusions based on the foregoing analysis. First, that there is a significant trend toward a view of knowledge as social action (a theme that has been highlighted in previous chapters), and which is rooted to context, and that “social action” can be understood as discourse (talk and text) in social interaction. Second, it is claimed that those theories classified as approaching “knowledge as social action” implicate in some way the KS thematic categories of identity, trust, risk, and context, while those which approach “knowledge as object” are more ambiguous. Third, although many theorists emphasize the central role of language and communication as the site of knowledge work, discourse itself is largely ignored as a serious location for research. Fourth, a theory of language is found to be all but absent from the KM field. This leads to the overall conclusion that focusing on research and analysis on organizational discourse, informed by a theory of language, holds the potential for a different approach to KM.

4.2 WHAT CONSTITUTES A THEORY?

Any investigator of the KM theoretical literature quickly becomes aware that there is relatively little use of the word “theory.” Instead, many use terms such as “framework.” Why the reticence? Patrick Lambe (private correspondence) suggests that it is the incommensurate, discipline-specific languages that underpin KM together with the lack of a single body of integrated theory, which leads to this unusual absence. The conventional scientific understanding of the meaning of “theory” is that it is an explanation and prediction about a state of affairs given a certain set of circumstances and that such predictions can be empirically tested and shown to be statistically probable or not. If this understanding of theory is adopted, then arguably quite a lot of what is loosely grouped together as KM “theory” would be considered problematical. So, a “looser” agenda is needed, opening the possibility of accepting as theory any work that describes itself as such or as a framework. However, the absence of the category “theory” is not the only absence.

A further observation of the KM theoretical literature is the reliance—as evidence—on what others have reported rather than the evidence of first-hand empirical research data. For instance, Tsoukas, in his robust arguments for a phenomenological framework of tacit knowledge, bases his principle largely on an exposition and interpretation of what Michael Polanyi wrote on the subject with no obvious reference to empirical research. Maria Jakubik, of the University of Applied Sciences in Finland, offers a new framework based around the notion of “becoming to know,” as a replacement in part of Nonaka and Takeuchi’s theory of the knowledge-creating firm. The evidence in support of her proposal is drawn from what others have theorized rather than empirical research findings. Where frameworks or theories do draw on evidence from field research, this tends to be of relatively limited scope in terms of, for instance, sample sizes or in their reliance on secondhand or anecdotal data.

There is in fact little evidence of empirical testing of KM theory. A recent review of 2175 journal articles published in the KM field reports the somewhat “shocking statistic” that only 0.33% of research actually involves field studies (see Further Reading). One notable exception is a study by Nonaka and coworkers, which investigates the hypothesis at the heart of Nonaka’s theory of organizational knowledge-creating. The study is based on an opportunity sample of 105 Japanese businessmen attending a seminar, and uses self-reporting questionnaires. The findings, it is claimed, provide strong support for the theory: “(T)tacit knowledge is thus mobilized through a dynamic ‘entangling’ of the different modes of knowledge conversion in a process which will be referred to as a ‘spiral’ model of knowledge creation” (1994 : 342). It is not made clear how this conclusion can be drawn from returned questionnaires using Likert-like scales, nor whether there are any alternative viable explanations for the findings. Is this an indication that for decades knowledge practitioners may have been pursuing strategies based on limited evidence?

4.3 AN APPROACH TO KNOWLEDGE MANAGEMENT’S THEORIES: A NOVEL TAXONOMY

An earlier review of the theoretical literature by Despres and Chauvel counts 72 different KM theories: they report that while there is little universal agreement over the nature of knowledge, similar to Heisig’s findings (see Section 1.2), there is a broad consensus across most theories that people are the cornerstone of KM (again, consistent with Heisig’s conclusions, as mentioned earlier). According to Despres and his colleague, the majority of KM theories approach knowledge as a social construct, and this raises the notion of knowledge as action-orientated. Following this finding, but with the proviso of not being in agreement with all of their conclusions (e.g., that organizational knowledge does not exist), it is proposed here that KM theory can be organized into the bisecting continua of “organizational knowledge versus personal knowledge” and “knowledge as object versus knowledge as social action” (see Figure 1). This is based on a critical review of almost 50 KM theories. Interestingly, Spender offers a similar formula, splitting the KM field into two “radically distinct domains,” one that unproblematically construes knowledge as object versus the other that not only rejects the whole idea of knowledge reification but also denies any transformation properties.

Knowledge management theories categorized on the bisecting continua of organizational focus vs. personal focus and knowledge as object vs. knowledge as social action with a total of 48 theories.

Figure 1 A taxonomy of knowledge management’s theories.

These continua are reflective of two of the most contentious debates in the theoretical literature: the question of whether knowledge should be approached from the perspective of it being personal or organizational, and whether it should be managed as an object, or approached as the product of social action. The former of these questions is the subject of some confusion, so will be returned to subsequently.

The sampling of KM theory (48 in total) on which this taxonomy is based is certainly not exhaustive. Each point on the axes in Figure 1 represents a theory or framework. (Note that this categorization was originally published in 2013, based on 36 theories and frameworks: the version here is considerably revised and extended.) As can be seen, a clear majority of theories are located along the “knowledge as social action” axis (26, two of which are credited to Frank Blackler, and five of which are considered to be “borderline”). This is consistent with, for instance, Charles Despres and his colleague’s findings in their review of KM theory. However, when one factors in that these are split based on their primary focus on personal or organizational knowledge, an inconsistency is revealed with the latter’s finding that theory, in the main, disputes the existence of organizational knowledge. This taps that issue mentioned earlier—the confusion over organization versus personal knowledge.

Those theories located on the axis line itself are interpreted as bilateral—their focus is both on knowledge as personal/organizational or knowledge as object/social action. By contrast, the group of theories occupying the knowledge as object space (17, five of which are credited to work by Professor Ikujiro Nonaka and colleagues) are all committed to a focus on organizational knowledge—which is logical. If a theory reifies knowledge as an object, it seems reasonable to conclude that knowledge is approached as an object (asset) of the organization.

Table 2 shows the detail of the source for Figure 1, with all theories shown chronologically to allow for the analysis of developing trends. According to this sampling, it is obvious that since the early 1990s the focus of theory has been overwhelmingly on organizational knowledge. Almost hidden is a steady “trickle” of perspectives, which advocate a focus on personal knowledge. What can also be seen are two clearly demarked camps—those who posit knowledge accomplished in social action and those who take a reductive approach. So while the KM that is accredited to Nonaka and his colleagues has, beyond doubt, proved the most influential and best known, there has been—working alongside—a persistent voice offering a radically different perspective. But why has this perspective not been adopted in practice with at least equal enthusiasm to the other? Perhaps the reason for this is very simple: despite a majority of theories locating knowledge in social action, this is often the only thing they have in common. Consequently, the alternative viewpoint to that advocated by Nonaka, his colleagues and supporters, is a fragmented one.

Table 2 Specifies the Source for Figure 1

Authors (Year) Main Focus Focus on Organization Focus on Personal Objectifying Social Action
Gaines (1989) Knowledge acquisition X X
Nonaka (1991, 1994)a The knowledge-creating company X X
Blackler (1993) Organizations as activity systems X X
Collins (1993) The structure of knowledge X X X
Blackler (1995) Activity theory and “knowing” X X
Nonaka and Takeuchi (1995) The knowledge-creating company X X
Nonaka et al. (1996) Technology in support of the knowledge-creating company X X
Quinn et al. (1996) Managing professional intellect X X
Spender (1996) Knowledge as the basis of a dynamic theory of the firm X X X
Grant (1996) Knowledge-based theory of the firm X X
Leonard and Straus (1997) Creative abrasion X (B) X (B)
Drucker (1998a) The coming of the new organization X X
Kleiner and Roth (1998) Learning histories X X (B)
Nonaka and Konno (1998) The concept of “Ba” as the foundation for knowledge creation X X
Brown and Duguid (1999) Architecture for organizational knowledge X X
Cook and Brown (1999) Generative dance between organizational knowledge and organizational knowing X X
Wenger (2000) Communities of practice and social learning systems X X
Markus (2001) Theory of knowledge reuse X X
Tsoukas and Vladimirou (2001) Organizational knowledge X X X
Earl (2001) “Schools” of knowledge management X X
Bhatt (2001) Knowledge management as an interaction between technologies, techniques and people. X X
Barabba et al. (2002) The organization as a system X X
Choo (2002) Organizational knowing X X
Boisot (2002) “I-Space”: creating and sharing knowledge X X X
Grant (2002) Knowledge-based view of the firm X X (B) X (B)
Leonard and Sensiper (2002) Tacit knowledge and innovation: the “innovation funnel” theory X X (B)
Snowden (2002) Complex acts of knowing: “Cynefin” X X X X
Jimes and Lucardie (2003) Reconsidering the tacit-explicit Distinction: the functional view theory of tacit knowledge X X X (B)
Schultze and Stabell (2004) Theory-based framework of assumptions about knowledge and its management X X X X
Thompson and Walsham (2004) Context as an inseparable art of knowing X X
Duguid (2005) “The art of knowing”: Communities of practice X X
Gourlay (2006) Knowing how and knowing that X X
Lytras and Pouloudi (2006) Framework for knowledge management from the learning perspective X X X
Leonard (2007) Transferring tacit knowledge within organizations X X
Prusak and Weiss (2007) Importance of social groups X X (B)
Lee and Lan (2007) Conversational collaboration and pillars of collaborative intelligence X X (B)
Ichijo (2007) Knowledge enablers X X
Buchel (2007) Creation and transfer of tacit knowledge within organizations X X
Nonaka and Toyama (2007) Theory of the knowledge-creating firm X X
Weber (2007) A new framework to address failure factors in repository-based knowledge management initiatives. X X
Ehin (2008) Unmanaging knowledge workers X X
Guzman (2009) Practical knowledge—a framework X X
Burford et al. (2011) The practice-based theory of knowledge X X
Jakubik (2011) Framework for knowledge creation: Becoming to know X X X
Rai (2011) Integrative framework for organizational knowledge management and organizational culture X X
Tsoukas (2011) Phenomenological framework for tacit knowledge X X
Quintane et al. (2011) Innovation as a knowledge based outcome: a new framework and definition X X
Crane and Bontis (2014) A new approach to tacit knowledge X X X

The “B” in brackets indicates that the selected classification is borderline.

a Nonaka’s 1991 and 1994 papers are included as one because they are more or less the same work.

Of course, this categorization of theory is entirely subjective in nature. It is not the case—unfortunately—that each author raises the rhetorical flag to mark their theory as treating knowledge as this or that, or that their focus is on organizational as opposed to personal knowledge. Such classifications are arrived at through an interpretive reading of the texts. As Paul Duguid succinctly points out in his treatise on the theory of Communities of Practice, no text is able to determine the rules of its own interpretation. In this view, no writer can precisely proscribe how the reader will interpret and understand their words, as this is in the minds of the readers. And that applies to all texts—whatever their nature.

The object/social action classification is based on how authors treat the subject of their theories: in some cases, notably Frank Blackler and Stephen Gourlay, the author expressly describes or implicates knowledge as social action, while with others it is more an interpretive choice based on the theorist’s descriptive and action language used to describe knowledge and how it is managed. On the organization/personal classification, the interpretation is more straightforward: is the theory/framework more focused on one or the other, or is it focused on both? Admittedly, a different analyst may arrive at a different interpretation.

The debate around the “personal versus organizational knowledge” question is the subject of some confusion in the literature and consequently merits a brief discussion.

4.4 THE PERSONAL VERSUS ORGANIZATIONAL KNOWLEDGE QUESTION

Many have asked whether knowledge can only ever be personal, or can it be organizational. This is possibly something of a red herring question. It is in the nature of things that each individual has knowledge that is personal to them and, equally obviously, an organization consists of individuals. So what of organizational knowledge? In fact, some scholars are critical of the emphasis on “knowing organizations.” Robert Grant, for one, suggests that such a conceptualization sidesteps the question on how individuals link their sets of knowledge to create this knowledge collective. Humans do not (yet) possess the ability to routinely connect their brains one directly to the other. So when some scientists talk about “linking our minds to others,” they are not talking about extrasensory perception. Rather, what is being described is the essential human propensity for collaboration and cooperation. So what is meant by “organizational knowledge”?

Professor Haridimos Tsoukas and his coworker address this very question (we touched on this work in Chapter 1). In their theoretical piece, which uses a single case study to illustrate their theory in practice, they investigate the links between personal and organizational knowledge, and human action in organizational contexts. They suggest that the lack of a theory of organizational knowledge, not least of knowledge itself, is responsible for definitional difficulties. They also note that the work of Michael Polanyi, on which much of the KM theorizing is based as we have seen in previous chapters, has not been well engaged with. Tsoukas and his colleague’s definition of personal knowledge is interpreted as the ability of the individual to apply their own understanding of context—consciously or not—and which ability mediates that individual’s actions in a given context: for instance, the formulation of a judgment, the solving of a problem, and so forth. This is slightly difficult to digest, but becomes clearer when we consider Tsoukas and his colleague’s formulation of organizational knowledge and their inferred distinction between this and personal knowledge.

Tsoukas and his coworker propose that organizational knowledge is the process by which people draw upon and act on a corpus of generalizations—generic rules produced by the organization, about which communities have shared meanings and based on which people formulate judgments. People understand these rules only by connecting them to their own informal judgmental capabilities, or personal knowledge. In this theory and interpretation, personal knowledge facilitates meaning for organizational knowledge, and which is inherently action-orientated. Recall Paul Duguid’s formulation of “knowing how” and “knowing that” introduced in Chapter 1 with the former described as the “art of practice.” In his thesis, “knowing how” informs or mediates knowing that, with the latter being incomprehensible without the former. Importantly, he also claims that “knowing that” does not produce “knowing how.”

Accordingly, and in a simpler analysis, personal knowledge is the ability, with organizational knowledge representing a process. Organizational knowledge cannot function without the other. The similarities with Duguid’s formulation are plain: personal knowledge equates to Duguid’s “knowing how,” which is the implicit ability to know how to act in a given set of circumstances, while organizational knowledge equates to his “knowing that,” which is the codifiable, explicit dimension that, of necessity, requires knowing how in order to function. But, and this is where such comparisons and contrasts become slippery and prone to misinterpretation, Duguid’s emphasis is on collectively shared knowledge, with the importance of a Community of Practitioners largely defined by its commonly shared tacit knowledge. Contrastingly, Tsoukas and his colleague emphasize the role of individual human judgment in arriving at “collective definitions.” There is a sheet of paper between these two perspectives. Conflating and simplifying both theoretical perspectives, individuals possess knowledge of the world, often held and used without conscious awareness, and which is the essential ingredient in making sense of the world and its contents. Organizational knowledge is the codifiable stuff, which organizations can produce as explicit content, or as enacted in shared understandings of how to behave, for instance, in a given circumstance. In other words, personal knowledge brings meaning to organizational knowledge. Personal knowledge can be unique to the individual, and it can fuel communally shared meanings, but, from a psychological perspective, what a person “knows” is fundamentally singular to the individual.

There are two important points to draw here. First, that personal knowledge or “knowing how” and organizational knowledge or “knowing that,” with an understanding of “organizational” in its broadest sense of community or even society, are tightly bound to one another with the latter dependent on the former for meaningful function. Second, Tsoukas and his coworker’s theory of the relationship between personal and organizational knowledge can be interpreted as implicating the four thematic categories earlier related to KS: context, identity, trust, and risk. While noting that their ideas draw heavily on the philosophical literature—in this case, Polanyi—which they adopt uncritically, their base of evidence is limited to one single case study with no detail given of the research methods or means of analysis. But as a discussion of the nature and relationship of personal versus organizational knowledge, it is a robust piece of rhetoric.

Taking a wider perspective, Robert Grant gives a critical account of the Knowledge-Based View of the Firm (KBVF). According to Grant, KBVF was developed in the 1990s based on the resource/capability analysis of the firm, epistemology, and organizational learning, all of which, he claims, have their focus on the role of knowledge as a “factor in production.” He argues that collective knowledge (viz., organizational knowledge) should be seen as an aggregation of the knowledge in people’s heads. But he goes on to warn that a focus on organizational knowledge risks reducing knowledge to the status of object. Thus, defining rules, procedures and such like as knowledge runs the risk of muddying the processes by which shared knowledge is evolved through human interaction (socialization). The upshot, he concludes, is of little use to managers in aiding them to “influence” these processes.

This particular perspective can be contrasted with that described by John Seely Brown and Paul Duguid who give primacy to organizational knowledge over personal knowledge. The contrast between these two versions of the KBVF operates at a fundamental level: Grant argues that firms exist to coordinate teams of specialist workers so that their knowledge may be integrated (reminiscent of Peter Drucker’s The Coming of the New Organization), whereas Brown and his colleague see the hard work of organizing knowledge as the important business of the organization. In their world, it is the firms that generate the knowledge with knowledge and practice inextricably linked. In Grant’s view, it is the individual who is the knowledge creator with firms in the role of “knowledge structures.” The key difference lies in the view of the organization: Brown and his coworker arguably perceive the organization as a “living system,” which echo’s Vincent Barabba and colleagues’ view of the organization as a system of parts that cannot be reduced to its individual elements. The alternative view offered by Grant is of the organization as a collection of structures that presumably could be reduced to its parts. What both impress on is the importance of knowledge to firms’ success, and an influencing role for technology.

So this is and is not a “red herring.” Arguably, the literature conflates two questions: that of whether knowledge is personal or organizational and that of whether the unit of analysis, as the focus of research and theory, should be at the personal or organizational level. In the taxonomy of KM theory included here, the personal versus organizational axis refers to the unit of analysis, not the implied or explicit stance of any given theory on the location of knowledge. That being understood, what does the taxonomy reveal about KM theory?

4.5 THE PERSONAL VERSUS ORGANIZATIONAL KNOWLEDGE ON THE SOCIAL ACTION AXIS

This section focuses on those theories classified along the “knowledge as social action” axis, grouping these into themes of inquiry. It would be impossible to exhaustively address all of the theories contained in the sampling, so discussions focus on those that are considered to be of most relevance and interest.

4.5.1 Personal Knowledge as the Unit of Analysis

As discussed earlier, Robert Grant is critical of those who subscribe entirely to organizational knowledge and is one of the few who make a clear reference to the “unit of analysis,” arguing that this should be the “person” not the organization. In this model, the goal is not knowledge transfer, but knowledge integration although one could argue that this is merely splitting hairs. Note, however, that Grant does not appear to dispute the existence of organizational knowledge, only that it should not be the focus of knowledge activities at the expense of personal knowledge.

Although the KBVF has been interpreted as a theoretical position, Grant himself questions whether it adds up to a singular theory. Nonetheless, according to Grant, it is the knowledge constitutive of persons that is the valued asset, and this can only be leveraged by integration through teamwork. By (borderline) implication, Grant, somewhat ironically, reifies knowledge as the object of integration mechanisms: rules and directives, sequencing, routines, group problem-solving, and decision-making. There is also a strong implication of the commodification of knowledge: “(K)knowledge is the overwhelmingly important productive resource in terms of market value…” (2002 : 136). Yet, if one sets aside those particular references, Grant is also arguably casting knowledge as social action in his emphasis on (social) integration practices as key to managing knowledge.

4.5.2 Knowledge as Practice Contrasted with Knowledge as Possession

Whereas Grant invokes the discourse of possession, Scott Cook and John Seely Brown of the Xerox Palo Alto Research Center in California, in their peculiarly named “generative dance” theory, take issue with this whole idea. They argue that such a discourse, with its implication of knowledge as something that people have, is limiting because it emphasizes one type of knowledge (explicit) above the other (tacit), resulting in a growing literature with a habit of explicitly or implicitly labeling knowledge as a typology of one. While there may be some truth in the latter statement, subsequent discussions reveal an opposite analysis to the notion of personal knowledge emphasizing the explicit. While Cook and his coworker’s theory is interpreted as approaching “knowing” as social action, their focus is more at organizational level in contrast to Grant’s approach.

In opposing an epistemology of possession, Cook and his colleague argue for an approach that views knowledge as a tool of knowing, with knowing connected to how we interact with the world. In their thesis, it is the interaction between knowing and knowledge that leads to the creation of new knowledge and “ways of knowing.” Thus, the term “generative dance” is coined and which is the source of all innovation. Their prescription is that knowledge is both used and grounded in action. Consequently, more attention should be paid to what knowledge work is done—in other words, practice. In effectively emphasizing knowledge accomplished in social interaction, and the action orientation of knowledge, are they that far apart from Grant’s emphasis on social integration practices? Not really. Brown and his colleague do arguably soften their case by proposing that epistemologies of possession and practice, while completely separate, are not incompatible. This immediately begs the question of why one would want to introduce a novel theory while clinging on to the traditionalist view. Nonetheless, the notion of knowing as action done in social contexts with knowledge as the requisite tool is generally consistent with a long line of theoretical development stretching back to the early 1990s and on to the present day. What they do not do is offer a perspective on how those “social contexts” come into being. At the most common-sense interpretative level, this idea implicates both the KS thematic categories of context and identity as a minimum.

There are two other points of interest to draw from the “generative dance” work: their criticism of the traditional scientific view of knowledge as something that must be sought, found, and articulated—in other words, knowledge as object—and their strong disagreement with the proposal that tacit knowledge can be converted to explicit and vice versa. This is the conversion process that lies at the heart of the influential theory of the knowledge-creating firm. Yet despite their position on the conversion issue, Cook and his colleague group this theory along with a number of other works, describing them as provocative and insightful.

The “generative dance” framework can be compared and contrasted with that proposed by Gustavo Guzman, of Griffith University, Australia, whose theory is interpreted as focusing on personal knowledge. He investigates the nature of practical knowledge, finding two opposing positions on this question: one approaches practical knowledge as stored in people’s heads, while the other sees it as situated in practice. Similarly to Cook and his coworker’s treatment of the ideas of possession and practice Guzman reasons that the two positions are not mutually exclusive. His theory, which has the aim of clarifying the confusing diversity of opinion, underlines the synergies between the cognitive and practice dimensions of knowledge using a simple case to make his point: it is the users of rules (as one form of knowledge) who determine when and how to use those rules. Thus, he makes the connection between knowledge how and knowledge that. Perspectives on those two concepts and their relationship are returned to presently.

According to this view, knowledge is seen as a multidimensional concept that can be personal, situated, and socially constructed at the same time. In terms of our KS thematic categories, if knowledge is personal, situated, and socially constructed, then it is bound to context and implicates identity with the aspects of “interpretation” and “determining” invoking notions of trust and risk.

Perhaps a more important contribution of Guzman’s proposal is that he treats dimensions of practical knowledge as “fuzzy”—they are not clear-cut categories but rather form a continuum. His aim is to explicate the various “quadrants” of practical knowledge, linking these to learning strategies with the objective of providing organizational managers with the ability to select the most appropriate learning strategy to suit the particular practical knowledge formula. In other words by road-mapping the type of practical knowledge that is to be shared or transferred between persons, the most effective learning approach can be selected and applied. Guzman’s theory of practical knowledge has some weight and rational validity, but it is entirely based on a review of the literature and it is not clear if the theory has been empirically tested.

Both of these theories invoke the idea of “Communities of Practice,” an influential notion that will be addressed in due course.

4.5.3 Connecting the “Organizational” with the “Personal”: Social, Situated, and Constructed

A number of theories that follow the notion of “knowledge as social action” and which are categorized as having a joint focus on both personal and organizational knowledge include those by Spender (1996), Tsoukas and Vladimirou, Boisot, Jakubik, and Crane and Bontis. Max Boisot’s “I-Space” theory of knowledge creation, similarly to Guzman’s project, emphasizes the importance of social learning as the foundation of knowledge creation, claiming that people do not share knowledge, rather they share information, which becomes knowledge once internalized to the individual. In Boisot’s model, knowledge is highly personal and relies on shared repertoires between individuals to reach common understandings (thus broadening the focus to the “organization”), which thesis has resonance with J.R. Searle’s influential notion of shared rules in speech acts, published in the late 1960s. The model can therefore be interpreted as having a joint focus both on the personal and organizational aspects of knowledge.

Although using different terminology, this theory is also consistent with the earlier account of organizational knowledge proposed by Tsoukas and his colleague, for instance. A divergence is Boisot’s leaning toward a cognitive understanding of knowledge with his emphasis on the cognitive effort in the form of abstraction and codification that is required in putting one’s knowledge into words such that it may be shared with others. This raises some interesting questions around people’s short- and long-term memory abilities, cognitive demand, limits on attention, and so forth, although a discussion of these does not feature in the framework and perhaps deservedly so as these are substantial topics for scientific research stretching back more than 100 years in the field of psychology alone. That aside, Boisot’s model, perhaps more strongly than others, foregrounds the role of identity, trust and risk, and context in the idea of “shared repertoires” and “common understandings.”

In something of a departure, Maria Jakubik’s “transformative teleology framework,” where “teleology” relates to a phenomenon’s end or purpose, proposes that the individual and social are not separated into different levels of organizational life. Instead, and with echoes of Guzman, knowledge is seen as embedded in human action, interactions, and situated practice. In her investigation of the relationship between knowledge creation and learning, she draws on the social view of learning defined by Etienne Wenger: “…learning is not located in individual heads, but in the processes of co-participation and in experiences. Learning can be seen as a social act, as a process of practice” (2011: 384). Wenger, an independent consultant, researcher, and author and who is credited along with Jean Lave with introducing the notion of “Communities of Practice” during the 1990s, claims that identity is a key structuring element in how we know because knowing is an act of belonging, referring here to Communities of Practice. In his account of these Communities as Social Learning Systems, Wenger also arguably invokes the importance of context. Two of the KS categories are therefore implicated here. What Wenger and Jakubik do not do, in the same vein as that noted in reference to Cook and Brown (1999) earlier and as found in most if not all KM theories, is explain how these social contexts, identity, and so forth come into being.

A fascinating account of the structure of knowledge is proposed by H. Collins. However as this does not really address KM per se, although it is included in the taxonomy because of its perceived importance, the commentary on this is restricted to the following. He posits two types of knowledge-relevant human action: regular acts that are normally associated with rule-following or rule-establishing and that can largely function at the unconscious level. Secondly, there are behavior-specific acts that are not really “acts” but more understood as behaviors, which can be articulated and therefore explicitly learned. One way of interpreting this is to apply the tacit/explicit labels, but this is perhaps to dilute the insight that Collins offers—the action-orientated, constructive nature of knowledge. And the implication of both context and identity as influencing factors.

What is beginning to emerge is the idea of knowledge being both inherently socially enacted, and as singular to the individual: it represents each person’s unique ability to de-code, interpret and make sense of their world without which socially enacted knowledge action could not and would not exist. Moreover, to a larger or lesser extent, many of the theories discussed so far can be interpreted as invoking categories of context, identity, trust, and risk (implicated earlier in Chapter 3 as factors in KS). Next, we review a number of KM theories located on the “knowledge as social action” axis, most of which focus on organizational knowledge: Activity Theory, the phenomenological perspective, “knowing how” and “knowing that,” Communities of Practice, and Creative Abrasion.

4.5.4 Knowledge, Activity Theory, and Activity Systems

Frank Blackler is responsible for some of the most insightful work in the field of KM—and some of the least recognized or understood. Blackler’s Knowledge and the Theory of Organizations is based on a modified version of Activity Theory, and like several others (e.g., Boisot), he emphasizes the central role of social learning. Activity Theory was originally proposed by the psychologist L.S. Vygotsky, working in the aftermath of the Russian Revolution. This constitutes people’s material actions and communications processes as the focus of study of human activity. These ideas locate the context of actions within “activity systems.” As Blackler caustically summarizes, “…the theory of organizations as activity systems offers an antidote to simplistic interpretations of the nature of individual knowledge and action, and organizational cultures and competencies” (1993 : 882).

In proposing that people construct themselves in action as a historically evolving process, Blackler is advocating a constructivist, action-orientated approach to knowledge. As such, he may be one of the first in this domain to refer to the idea of “identity construction.” He is critical of the mainstream rational-cognitive approaches to KM in their reification of knowledge and assumption of the rationality of both organization and individual. Interestingly, Philip Selznick, of the University of California, in his Foundations of the Theory of Organization, published in 1948, formulates the organization as a cooperative system of rational action, which is at risk from the “indiscipline” or irrationality of its participants!

As touched on in Section 1.4, Blackler draws on the work of H. Collins speculating a shift away from knowledge as situated in bodies and routines (embodied, embedded) toward knowledge as situated in brains (embrained), dialogue (encultured), and symbols (encoded). In other words, a move from knowledge as objective, tangible, and routinizable, to knowledge as constituted in social action. Thus the unit of analysis should be the socially distributed activity system within which knowing is done. He further emphasizes the importance of language in such systems, referring to it as the “archetypal communal activity” without which action would not be possible. From this perspective, the five-image framework of knowledge that Blackler had earlier seemed to espouse, he now sees as lacking. Instead, Blackler argues that the lens of research, practice and analysis should be on the activity systems in which knowledge is socially done: knowledge as mediated (e.g., through language), situated (in context), provisional (constantly developing) and contested (the subject of power relations). A clear reference can be drawn from Blackler’s theory to the KS categories of context and identity, with the implication of trust and risk. Moreover, the connection between these “actions” and language is made explicit.

Blackler is an early advocate of what could be described as a postmodernist approach to KM. (A core tenet of postmodernism is that knowledge is constructed rather than discovered through, for instance, observation, and is the means of power). Blackler positions his theory as a critical reaction to mainstream conventions (the “rational-cognitive” approach), although unfortunately his work has been largely overlooked in the field. Nonetheless, the view of knowledge as socially actioned has many proponents as shown in the taxonomy, and many of which emphasize the pivotal role of communications: these are, for instance, landmarked in the late 1980s by Gaines, the late 1990s by Drucker and in the more recent work of theorists including Tsoukas, which is discussed next.

4.5.5 The Phenomenological Perspective

Haridimos Tsoukas’ Phenomenological View of Tacit Knowledge quite clearly has a focus on personal knowledge, with its ideas grounded in those theorized by Michael Polanyi. As discussed in Section 1.4, far from theorizing about KM, Polanyi’s 1962 work, Personal Knowledge: Towards a Post-Critical Philosophy, is in fact an argument for turning away from the traditional view and practice of the exact sciences and its pursuit of objective knowledge and scientific detachment. Instead, he posits the importance of the scientist—the “knower”—in the act of discovery and validation of scientific knowledge. Drawing on Polanyi’s reasoning, Tsoukas criticizes the contemporary movement toward the decontextualization of knowledge. In his phenomenological approach to tacit knowledge he argues that explicit knowledge cannot exist without the tacit. This personal co-efficient factor suggests that all knowing—which implies the actual and potential to know residing in the individual’s head—is rooted to some context and action. It is important to note here that Tsoukas’ theory is centered on personal knowledge as an action-orientated phenomenon as opposed to a global understanding of knowledge (e.g., written knowledge). Resonance with many earlier works is clear. In this, context emerges as essential to knowing action.

Tsoukas is a particular critic of Nonaka’s theory of the knowledge-creating firm, devoting a substantial part of his paper to its unraveling. In his criticism, Tsoukas is not alone.

4.5.6 “Know(ing) How” and “Know(ing) That” and Communities of Practice

In his conceptualization of knowledge creation (and scathing criticism of “Nonaka’s theory”), Stephen Gourlay stands aside from the mainstream’s general acceptance of the tacit and explicit components of knowledge. Instead, he offers an explanation based on the concepts of “know how” and “know that.” This sounds familiar: recall, for instance, Paul Duguid’s use of similar terms, although there are some differences notably in Duguid’s preference for “knowing how/that” (see Section 1.4) and Guzman’s theory of practical knowledge. In Gourlay’s thesis, “know how” is rooted in and characteristic of everyday life, some of which is not capable of articulation, whereas “know that” emerges from the processes of reflecting and theorizing. A further distinction is that Gourlay views both of these concepts as behaviors. He reasons that in order to manage knowledge one must do so indirectly by managing behavior. This, he warns, raises a new panoply of issues and the potential to destroy that which management seeks to control (see Section 2.6 for a discussion around ethics and KM). Again, an interpretive view implicates the four KS thematic categories of context, identity, trust, and risk: that is, “know how” rooted in everyday life (context), “know that” as an outcome of reflection, and theorizing (identity), which collectively with the notion of behavior gives rise to the potential for trust and risk.

Like Blackler, Gourlay’s reasoning is consistent with postmodernist thinking and has particular relevance to the discussions around Implicit Learning in Chapter 7. Note also the synergies with the ideas proposed by, for instance, Tsoukas, through the emphasis on knowing as behavior, connecting knowledge—knowing something—to action. That said, his conceptualization of “know how” and “know that” is no doubt the source of some confusion when the attempt is made to compare this with Paul Duguid’s conceptualization, for instance. It is to Duguid and his colleague’s work, arguably more influential than that of Gourlay, that we now turn.

Communities of Practice (CoPs) lie at the heart of John Seely Brown and Paul Duguid’s architecture for organizational knowledge. In this, knowledge is mostly collective with successful CoPs being informal in nature, resonant of Etienne Wenger’s claim for the primacy of the informal over the formal. Ironically their architecture is largely dominated by themes of command and control. For instance, they emphasize the “organizing” work of firms, which contrasts with Robert Grant’s view that the organization exists to foster and coordinate an environment in which individuals can integrate their personal knowledge with that of others. Brown and Duguid view the organization as the means of knowledge generation and see organizational knowledge as more important than personal knowledge—the sum is greater than its parts, which once again recalls Vincent Barabba and colleagues’ systemic view of the organization. Their Architecture for Organizational Knowledge is largely about interfirm communications and the establishment of human, technological, and process-based conduits through which a team’s knowledge can be shared among other teams. For example, they propose that “translators,” people who are attached to more than one team group, are important transports for knowledge between groups in a kind of cross-fertilization process.

Originally introduced in the early 1990s, Communities of Practice theory has proved immensely influential but frequently misused according to Duguid writing in the mid-2000s. Emphasizing the inherently social substance of CoP theory, he conjures the CoP as the stage on which the shared “knowing how” of the community is on display, not just that of its individual members. His explication of CoP theory is largely concerned with dispelling the “myth” that tacit knowledge can or should be converted to the explicit. Equating “knowing how” to tacit knowledge as the “art of the knowing,” which he importantly constructs as the action of “learning to be,” and “knowing that” to explicit knowledge as the action of “learning about,” he reasons that to attempt to transform the former into the latter will likely lead to a transformation of learning to be into learning about. The profound importance of this lies in the simple analogy: “learning to be” is the art of knowing; of becoming a member of a Community of Practice, for instance; or of assimilating an art from a mentor over time. “Learning about” is equivalent to reading from books. To use Duguid’s reasoning, one does not become an accountant by reading an accountancy textbook. One must learn from a master.

Duguid’s ideas have considerable significance for the ideas developed here and in subsequent parts of the book. To complete this section, we make a brief visit to the intriguingly named Theory of Creative Abrasion.

4.5.7 Creative Abrasion

Dorothy Leonard and her colleague, writing in 2002 , are also interested in people sharing knowledge in group work. Their Theory of Creative Abrasion frames the different backgrounds, skills, experiences, and understood social norms that individuals have as the factors that generate the melting pot of innovation. In this implied chaotic environment, people will challenge each other leading to an abrasion of different ideas, which in turn give rise to new ones. Their explanation of this outcome is simple: people will search for novel solutions to problems when they are exposed to ideas and perspectives which “challenge” the majority’s prevailing wisdom. Moreover, it is the tacit dimension of an individual’s knowledge, learned through practice, not capable of articulation, which formulates them as valuable contributors to group work and innovation. From a pragmatist’s perspective, this thesis does rely on the majority group within any given organizational community being, in the first instance, open to novel concept: this cannot be simply assumed. But it does have an interesting connection to Chris Argyris’ notion of Double Loop Learning (DLL), which we will come to shortly.

As a basic idea, this is not entirely divorced from the concepts of social learning advocated elsewhere. It sits on the organization end of the organization versus personal knowledge continuum through its focus on the organization—teams of workers—as the unit of analysis. From their perspective, the individual is problematic in the tendency to hoard tacit knowledge and reluctance to share knowledge through fear of failure or of looking foolish. A further point to draw is their acknowledgment of the need for a cross-disciplinary approach to understanding knowledge and innovation: “(C)clearly, many different fields of inquiry are relevant, including ones as diverse as design, cognitive psychology, group dynamics and information technology” (Leonard and Sensiper, 2002: 495). It sounds complicated, but this theory does have echoes of Peter Drucker’s visionary piece on the future organization comprising teams of specialists dedicated to specific projects. It also has resonance with the KS categories of interest—context (teamwork), identity (team membership), trust, and risk.

An earlier piece of work by Leonard and coworker Susaan Straus takes a more general, higher-level viewpoint arguing that innovation, of necessity, requires a mixture of different styles of human thinking. Accordingly, innovation will not emerge among teams of like-minded individuals. Wenger (2000) makes a similar point. Innovation needs conflict. Consequently, organizations need the means of determining thinking styles and preferences, and for that, psychometric tests are recommended. While their reasoning is logical, the implication that individuals be assessed for thinking style and appointed based on this assessment inevitably raises some ethical concerns. Leonard and Strauss’ ideas can be interpreted as orienting to “knowledge as social action” through their emphasis on social interaction, with consequences for knowledge as an action category.

We now turn to the “knowledge as object” end of the continuum, noting how this end of the field is largely dominated by one theory.

4.6 REIFICATION OF KNOWLEDGE: ONE PARADIGM DOMINATES

Those theories that explicitly, or by implication, reify knowledge all focus on the organizational level. This section mainly focuses on the Dynamic Theory of Organizational Knowledge Creation/Knowledge-Creating Firm, and its various manifestations (“the theory”). It has been so heavily criticized over the years, with almost no element left unchallenged, that only a brief account of the theory itself is given to begin with. Most of the discussions then focus on an analysis of some of the major points of criticism brought against it.

4.6.1 “The Theory” and the Theorist as Bricoleur

The driving force behind the theory, according to Nonaka, writing in 1994 , is a reaction against the then dominant conventional conceptualization of the organization as a static, passive, “input–process–output” system. According to his radical (at the time) reasoning, building an action-orientated understanding of the organization means attending to two key aspects of the organization itself: its interaction with the environment in which it operates (and presumably those in which it would like to operate) and the ways and means by which it creates and communicates knowledge and information. These are ranked as the most important features of the organization. In effect, what Nonaka aims to do is to shift the emphasis from how the organization processes information and knowledge to how it creates it. That is surely a worthy ambition and appropriate to the emergence of the “knowledge society.”

A noticeable feature of the theory is the number of other theories and philosophical works that it draws on from across a wide range of disciplines (subsequent discussions address several of these): for instance, JR Searle’s “Speech Acts” (philosophy of language), John Anderson’s “Adaptive Control of Thought” architecture of cognition (cognitive psychology), Polanyi’s philosophy of knowledge, Chris Argyris’s “DLL” theory (organizational behavior), John Seely Brown and Paul Duguid’s (version of) “Communities of Practice” (knowledge management), A.E. Scheflen’s work in “Interaction Rhythms” (communications behavior), and introduced in 1998, the concept of “Ba” derived from the works of two Japanese philosophers. Now, there is nothing wrong in drawing on the works of others, and indeed the majority of academic writing does precisely this. But this particular treatment suggests something of the theorist as “bricoleur.”

At the heart of the theory is the SECI model that explains knowledge creation as the outcome of a dynamic interaction between subjectivities and objectivities. Accordingly, new knowledge is created in a spiral of interaction between the processes of socialization, externalization (explicit knowledge), combination, and internalization (tacit knowledge). Despite its emphasis on the socialization principle (indeed, Nonaka’s theory is one of the very few to make a direct reference to a theory of language, namely, JR Searle’s Speech Acts), the theory is positioned at the “knowledge as object” end of the axis because of its central tenet that tacit knowledge can and should be converted to explicit knowledge in the fashion proposed by the SECI model. It is for this “conversion” process that it is most heavily criticized. The product of this theory is a view of knowledge reified as an object to be managed and converted. According to David Snowden, Nonaka and his colleagues conceptualize knowledge creation as the output of a process that passes knowledge from the individual onto the group, and from the group to the organization, and thence to wherever else it needs to or can be transferred to. This, he claims, is quite obviously a reified view of knowledge as the object of management that at some point in the SECI process can be rendered explicit. A further question is this: in a theory that sets out to explain and predict organizational knowledge creation, is it not essentially wedded to “process”?

The inherent irony is that while Nonaka and his coworkers emphasize the importance of tacit knowledge, implying its possession of greater value than the explicit variety, the mandate to convert tacit to explicit knowledge signals a consequential devaluation of the former—it is only useful if transformed to the explicit. As Charles Despres and his colleague somewhat dramatically phrase it: “(T)the root idea is that knowledge becomes only useful when it goes into the forge of social interaction” (2002: 93). A dissenting voice to this interpretation is Snowden, who claims that the SECI model does not mandate that all knowledge in people’s heads and conversations should or could be made explicit. However in this, Snowden stands out from a majority of scholars critical of the SECI model. Note that in later versions of the theory (see, for instance, Nonaka and Toyama, 2007) an explicit reference is made to an “interaction” between explicit and tacit knowledge, but the conversion mandate remains at its core, thus arguably diluting the reference to “interaction.”

The idea that new knowledge can be generated in this dynamic interaction between two types of knowledge representing the subjective and the objective, and which process is fertilized and promoted in the socially engineered environment of “Ba,” has been the target of considerable criticism.

4.6.2 Shuffling Ideas

Critics include Charles Despres and his coworker who condemn theories including Nonaka’s for being too prescriptive and, with their ideas based around “transformations and dynamics,” imply these represent nothing more than the shuffling of ideas back and forth in structures and systems. According to Mark Thompson and his coworker, the very notion of knowledge transformation leads to a contradiction because “…the meaning of any objective ‘knowledge’ will always remain the subjective product of the person in whose mind this is constituted, always relationally defined, and therefore does not transfer easily to others in a form which may be operationalized to the benefit of the organization” (2004 : 726: italics in original).

In this way, they invoke and promote the importance of context, reasoning that attempts to “transfer” knowledge are unlikely to lead to organizational success. Support for this perspective can be seen in Ilkka Virtanen’s review of the literature, which reports that most Information and Communications Technologies (ICT) focused KM initiatives aim to convert tacit to explicit knowledge—and most fail.

As well as being criticized for its focus on the organization (at the expense of the individual), coupled with the reification and decontextualization of knowledge, the theory is censured for its ambiguity on the one hand and explicit distinction between knowledge and learning on the other. For instance, many would disagree with his proposal that learning is a static and limited concept (as noted earlier in Section 2.3.3) compared with the more dynamic and conceptually broader idea of knowledge creation. As discussed in Section 3.6, knowledge is elsewhere posited as a subset of learning.

Stephen Gourlay, perhaps one of the most outspoken critics of the theory, is certainly not alone in devoting much of his work on Conceptualizing Knowledge Creation to dissecting the theory, seeking to demonstrate the shifting sands and miscalculations on which is it is based. He specifically points to the “cracks in the engine” of the SECI model, arguing that this is more a theory of managerial decision-making than knowledge creation. On Nonaka’s evidence in support of the validity of the theory, Gourlay comments that this in reality represents nothing more than what managers believe to be the source of new ideas.

4.6.3 Misinterpretation and Misrepresentation

Perhaps most problematic is the suggestion that Nonaka and his colleagues have misinterpreted and misrepresented the works of Michael Polanyi in what Haridimos Tsoukas refers to as the “great misunderstanding” (see also Section 1.4 for additional discussions around this issue). As the core foundation of the theory draws on Polanyi’s work on the nature of knowledge this is a significant issue. The primary sticking point is over the nature of tacit knowledge. Polanyi proposes that all knowledge is personal, involves judgment, and that all knowledge contains a tacit element, which is often difficult if not impossible to articulate. According to Tsoukas, this establishes the contextual and action-orientated nature of knowing. However, Nonaka’s interpretation is slightly—but crucially—different: “Polanyi classified knowledge into two categories. ‘Explicit’ or codified knowledge refers to knowledge that is transmittable in formal, systematic language. On the other hand, ‘tacit’ knowledge has a personal quality which makes it hard to formalize and communicate” (Nonaka, 1994: 16, italics added).

In his analysis of Nonaka and his various coworkers’ interpretation of the works of Polanyi, Tsoukas is critical of their emphasis on reducing practical knowledge (viz., tacit knowledge) to “precisely definable content.” In other words, the aim of collecting knowledge located in people’s heads and “translating” this to explicit knowledge will achieve little more than reduce the value of that knowledge by converting what is known to that which is representable. This is precisely the argument that Paul Duguid and others imply in their view that ‘knowing that’ does not produce ‘knowing how’. So, while the theory draws on Polanyi’s ideas, the interpretation and representation of it—particularly the nature of tacit knowledge and its potential for conversion to explicit knowledge—is allegedly misrepresentative.

A related issue is highlighted by Kenneth Grant, following an earlier piece of work in which Grant and his coworker conclude that Polanyi’s theory concerning the tacit/explicit question has been largely misunderstood. Grant hypothesizes that many researchers in the KM field who refer to Polanyi have not actually read the source material, but are instead relying on others’ interpretation. This combined with a less than critical approach to the work of Nonaka and his colleagues, suggests Grant, is one of the underpinning reasons for KM’s lack of success.

As mentioned at the outset, the theory makes reference to the works of two other leading and influential theorists: Chris Argyris’s DLL in Organizations and John Anderson’s Architecture of Cognition (ACT theory). In both instances, it can be shown that Nonaka appears to misrepresent these works in how they are used to support his ideas. Argyris’ theory of DLL is essentially concerned with the need for senior managers to continuously challenge organizational policies, procedures, visions, objectives—as people’s internal theories of action—and so on in order to ensure progress and development. If not, firms will remain in a status quo and will eventually be overcome by others. According to Nonaka, firms find it difficult to implement DLL themselves, but, fortunately, it is “built in” to his theory. In reality, the only potential point of synergy between this theory and the theory of DLL is Nonaka’s parole that managers should challenge what employees know. However, Argyris is primarily talking about manager’s own internal theories of action based on organizational dictates, while Nonaka is talking about third parties challenging knowledge in other people’s heads—and how the latter interpret organizational dictates, for example. Arguably, then, DLL is not “built in” to the theory of the knowledge-creating firm.

The theory also draws on a 1983 version of Anderson’s ACT Model, however the later 1996 version published by Anderson suffices for the purpose here. In this, declarative memory (which Nonaka equates to explicit knowledge) is a schema like structure encoding a small bundle of knowledge, whereas procedural memory (equated to tacit knowledge) is applied automatically, is tied to context and can often not be articulated. Anderson proposes that complex cognitions are the result of interactions between declarative and procedural knowledge: “(A)all that there is to intelligence is the simple accrual and tuning of many small units of knowledge that in total produce complex cognition. The whole is no more than the sum of its parts, but it has a lot of parts” (1996: 356). He also claims that production rules that embody procedural knowledge can create declarative structures, but not the other way around. (This has echoes in Paul Duguid’s argument that knowing how cannot be derived from knowing that.) Note the use of the term “interactions” to describe the relationship between these two forms of knowledge/memory.

Interestingly, according to one interpretation of Anderson’s model, skill compilation leads to new skill acquisition, making knowledge a subset of learning (consistent with Krathwohl’s account of Bloom’s Taxonomy), whereas Nonaka’s theory constitutes learning as a subset of knowledge. Nonaka also clearly states that in Anderson’s theory declarative knowledge is transformed into procedural knowledge: “(T)the idea of ‘knowledge conversion’ may be traced from Anderson’s ACT model…” (1994: 18). This is not a strictly accurate account of Anderson’s own version of affairs in its introduction of the notion of “transformation” (viz., conversion), which is entirely absent from Anderson’s.

Note that both DLL and ACT are absent from the SECI model in versions subsequent to 1994.

4.6.4 More Troubling Observations on the Theory of the Knowledge-Creating Firm

Analogous with Brown and Duguid’s and Wenger’s conceptualization of Communities of Practice, the theory describes the “informal community” as the location of emerging knowledge. He goes on to suggest that these need to be integrated into the formal hierarchical structure of the organization. This implies a transformation of the informal to the formal. Would this not lead to a loss of the values and benefits afforded through informally organized work groups? Moreover, the scholar Charles Ehin, of Westminster College Utah, in his framework for “unmanaging” knowledge workers, claims that the formalization of communities of practice within a top-down hierarchical structure does not work. This mirrors a view previously promoted by Wenger.

Expanding on this theme of “communities,” a key claim made is that the theory is cross-cultural. This is difficult to substantiate particularly in the light of the nature of the theory. Recall that the theory is originally developed based on observations of Japanese firms. As is widely theorized elsewhere, knowledge is inextricably bound to culture (as context). Following H. Collins’ The Structure of Knowledge, culture undeniably varies from organization to organization, from community to community, from nation to nation, and so forth and so will the following of rules (see Section 3.5 for a discussion of this issue). The “one-size-fits-all” approach does not sit well with this conceptualization.

To complete this critical review, the theory’s stance on the temporal/cognitive nature of knowledge raises some interesting questions. The theory proposes that tacit knowledge refers to future events (with the inference that it only can refer to the future), while explicit knowledge deals with the past. Further, only tacit knowledge comprises cognitive elements. There is no evidence for this claim, and arguably, even if one takes the view that tacit knowledge is internalized, comprising skills, difficult to articulate, and the “more than we can tell” element of knowledge, why can tacit knowledge not refer to the past and present as well as the future? Additionally, if, as Polanyi argues, all knowledge contains a tacit element, then it is not logical to propose that explicit knowledge is bereft of cognitive components nor that it can only refer to events in the past.

With respect to the KS thematic categories of context, identity, trust, and risk, this theory arguably offers an ambiguous view: for instance, context from one direction is valued (e.g., social interaction, “Ba”), but then devalued from another (culture is irrelevant and can be “crossed,” the conversion model). Despite these difficulties, the theory continues to dominate the KM theoretical landscape with numerous other theorists following in its wake in one fashion or another, mainly through an uncritical acceptance and adoption of the tacit/explicit explanation at its heart.

4.7 ROUNDUP OF SOME OTHER PERSPECTIVES IN THE “KNOWLEDGE AS OBJECT” SPECTRUM

Of those theories categorized at the “knowledge as object” end of the axis, the following brief review focuses on four, which are considered to be both interesting and of some value to the organizational manager. (This is a subjectively based selection and is not meant to indicate the inadequacy, in any way, of other theories.) Michael Earl (2001), professor of IM at the London Business School, offers an account of “schools of KM.” He uses the analysis of case studies, interviews, workshops, and published materials to develop his “taxonomy of KM strategy.” This proposes three schools of KM—technocratic, economic, and behavioral—each of which is designed to apply to different types of organization, including descriptions of how they might work in practice. Despite the selective, subjective, and interpretive nature of his methodology, Earl’s work can be seen as a practical aid for knowledge managers which at least acknowledges that there are many “flavors” of KM, in contrast to the “one-size-fits-all” accounts.

In her account, Dorothy Leonard considers ways in which knowledge is transferred within organizations, and the associated barriers. Like many other theorists, she draws on case studies in the literature and her own anecdotes to give substance to her proposals. Leonard is notably one of the few theorists to highlight the difference between knowledge that is transferred and knowledge that is reused. The knowledge that is transferred from its host will not be the same as that which is admitted by the recipient. This is because knowledge will become adapted, claims Leonard, as the recipient indexes it to their preexisting knowledge and experience. The problem with transferring tacit knowledge, she reasons, lies in its “stickiness”—that is, the difficulty of separating knowledge from its source citing cultural effects, tensions in attempting to apply rigid coding contrasted with ambiguity of knowledge, and the knowledge gaps between transmitter and receiver. The subject matter of Leonard’s framework, and her treatment of it, implies knowledge as an object in contrast to her other work mentioned elsewhere that does not. That aside, there is the notable reprise of categories seen in the “knowledge as social action” side of the debate in the idea of stickiness and cultural effects (context), knowledge gaps between knowers (identity), and connotations of trust and risk that these imply.

Leonard’s cognitive perspective can be compared with Hong Kong-based Professor Lynne Markus’ theory of knowledge reuse. In what is clearly a “systems approach” to KM, Markus advises that KM should only be concerned with explicit knowledge, emphasizing the importance of “organizational memory systems” such as IT repositories. Markus’ theory proposes that different knowledge reuse situations require different approaches: so, for instance, producers and users of shared work have different needs, which makes sense. However, this work is an example of what some have insisted is at the heart of KM’s issues—a concentrated focus on IT. As discussed elsewhere, many have connected the commitment to KM technologies to the risk of failure (see, for instance, Sections 2.5 and 3.3). That aside, Markus’ theory does implicate the influence of context. Rosina Weber, of Dexel University, Philadelphia, admits the construction of enormous organizational memory systems stands as 1 of the 15 factors leading to KM failure. In addressing this issue, she suggests a framework for how technology should be approached, adopted, and implemented in organizations (e.g., design input from end users). This might be of particular use and interest to the organizational manager.

It would be remiss to complete this round-up without a brief review of David Snowden’s Complex Acts of Knowing. Unusually, this is categorized across all taxonomy quadrants: that is, it treats knowledge both as an object (“thing” to use Snowden’s word) and action (a “flow”), spreading its focus across both organizational and personal knowledge. In his Cynefin model, he offers four “domains” of knowledge: bureaucratic, professional, informal, and uncharted. According to Snowden, the model’s purpose is to facilitate sense-making as an aid to decision-making, leadership, and so forth. While Snowden’s model may not represent a KM theory in the conventional sense, what it does do is step the “convention” beyond the management of knowledge for its self-serving sake to knowledge and its management as a fundamental building block in any organizational activity.

Two pragmatic points raised by Snowden are worth noting: first, he argues that the number of informal and formal communities in any large organization prohibits their formal management, a perspective that can be contrasted with Nonaka’s advice to formalize all such communities. Secondly he suggests, perhaps somewhat controversially, that the knowledge that exists within the “informal space” should not necessarily be seen as an asset of the organization. In other words, KM need not concern itself with every workplace community, nor should it attempt to print its ownership on all knowledge that walks in and out of the doors each day. Neither will bring advantage to decision-making, problem-solving, and leadership, for instance.

One characteristic that Snowden’s model shares with all other KM theories discussed here is the absence of a specified theory of language despite, in his case, an emphasis on culture. Even those theories and frameworks, which directly emphasize the importance of language, with knowledge understood as accomplished in social action, there is no reference to a theory of discourse—with the exception of Nonaka’s theory, of course.

In terms of the thematic categories of context, identity, trust, and risk, most of the foregoing is ambiguous. To a larger or lesser extent, one might arguably suggest a common implication of the notion of “context,” but here that is predominantly framed as the context of the environment and its contents (e.g., IT system) influencing the human participants. The exception is Leonard.

Continuing in the pragmatic theme, there is one more feature of KM theory that needs to be discussed: the inductionist basis.

4.8 THE ISSUES OVER THE INDUCTIONIST FOUNDATION OF THEORY

Arguably, KM’s most influential theories are in fact largely inductive in nature. Nonaka’s theory, for instance, is developed from observations of Japanese firms. This raises the question of their validity. According to Karl Popper, perhaps the most famous critic of inductionism, its crime is to construct “universal truths” based on single instances of experience (observation). In his immensely popular book What Is This Thing Called Science?, Professor Alan Chalmers argues that no two observers watching the same scene or object will perceive it in exactly the same way. The logical inference of this is a relational chain of culpability: if observation can be subject to error, what chance for the facts that it produces, and the scientific knowledge that is constructed on those facts? Recall the case of the Royal Astronomer discussed in Section 1.3, and how two observers of the same phenomena are found to record different accounts. Professor Thomas Kuhn’s equally influential treatise, The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, argues along much the same lines. Kenneth Gergen also claims that there can be no such thing as objective observation, subsequently developing his ideas in the direction of universal relational being.

As many KM theories take scientific enquiry and knowledge as their basis, it is appropriate to bring the scientific perspective to bear. If the inductionist approach to theory development involves extracting “facts” from observation, and then developing a theory to explain them, and it can be shown that those “facts” can be wrong, where does this leave the theory? Specific to Nonaka’s claim for cultural transcendence, the facts observed and used to construct theory are drawn from firms operating in Japanese culture. Would the same facts be observed in a different cultural environment? Or, for that matter, by American observers of Japanese companies? Would individual observers arrive at different accounts? These fascinating topics are addressed in more detail in Part Two (Chapter 11).

No apologies are made for giving over so much space to a discussion of one single KM theory. As this is the dominant perspective and paradigm, as both influencer and subject of criticism, an understanding of the “Nonaka” phenomenon is essential to understanding the KM theoretical landscape. There are, of course, many more theories in the KM field, but this nonexhaustive review of the theory literature gives a flavor of the ground covered, and issues raised.

4.9 SUMMARY AND CONCLUSIONS

The KM domain of theory is broad, complex, sometimes ambiguous, and often confusing. To bring some clarity, theories are classified into the broad categories of “personal versus organizational knowledge” and a view of “knowledge as object” or as “accomplished in social action.” This classification reveals a significant anomaly. On the one hand, the most dominant and influential theory and its various evolutions, collectively grouped as The Knowledge-Creating Company, is interpreted as reifying knowledge as object and as having a focus on the organizational unit of analysis, as do a number of other theories. On the other hand, there is a visible trend toward the view of knowledge as social action, but none of its theories or frameworks has achieved the popularity and recognition assigned to The Knowledge-Creating Company. Added to this is the perspective that KM has yet to achieve the kind of success that one would expect from a discipline and practice that concentrates on what is widely seen as an organization’s most important asset.

It has also been shown how the KM theoretical landscape is often the sparring ring of considerable debate, contradiction and dissent, with accusations of misinterpretation and misrepresentation constituting a characteristic hall-mark. In part, these issues emanate from the substantial assumptions on which many theories rest: that knowledge can be identified as a singular thing or activity, that KM outcomes can be measured in some way, that the tacit can be made explicit and vice versa, that this phenomenon called knowledge resides in people’s heads, but that they must be motivated to share it. Many assume that language, communication, and social interaction are important, but how is not specified; that what will work in one culture or organization will—or will not—work in another; and finally, that with the right organizational structure, knowledge can be commanded and controlled.

One question lingers: how and why did the theoretical works of Nonaka and his colleagues achieve such “superstar” status? One can only speculate. Perhaps one reason is that these works are more accessible—more easily understood and more resonant of modern organizational thinking—than some of those on offer.

From the discussions around organizational knowledge, and particularly drawing on the works of Haridimos Tsoukas and his colleague, and Paul Duguid, it is reasoned that personal knowledge and organizational knowledge are tightly connected, with the latter dependent on the former. It is the personal component that illuminates and brings meaning to the organizational experience, as indeed it has been speculated elsewhere that it does with all aspects of life. This is an idea that is developed as we proceed through the rest of this book, culminating in an explication and illustration of exactly how this works in everyday life.

Four final points can be drawn.

  • First, that the thesis of “knowledge as social action” invokes an understanding of “social action” as discourse (talk and text) in interaction.
  • Second, that while those theories and frameworks shown to occupy the “knowledge as social action” end of the taxonomy axis can be interpreted as implicating, to some degree, the thematic categories of context, identity, trust, and risk, previously identified (see Chapter 3) as categories relevant to KS, those on the “knowledge as object” axis are far more ambiguous in this respect.
  • Third, that while some of the “knowledge as social action” based theories explicitly orient to the importance of language—variously understood as communication, discourse, talk, and text in social interaction—and others imply this, none (in this sampling) have optioned discourse in the organizational context as a viable and relevant site for research.
  • Finally, and extending the latter point, a theory of language is also shown to be all but absent (one exception being, ironically, Nonaka’s Dynamic Theory of Organizational Knowledge Creation in its reference to Searle’s Speech Act Theory), in spite of some scholars’ emphasis on the import of language.

To conclude, if KM is not perceived to have achieved any significant measure of recognized success in practice—as some have argued—then there is perhaps room for a different approach. If there is a demonstrable trend toward the view of knowledge as constructed in social interaction, along with the implied importance ascribed to language and communication, then it would seem logical to turn in this direction, for the purposes of the research project research project here: language and talk as the site of action.

The next chapter moves the debate in the direction of social psychology, social constructionism, and discourse analysis with a particular interest in discursive psychology. We consider how the latter—the study and analysis of human linguistic actions as accomplished in everyday talk-in-interaction—could represent both a valid, even novel (within the KM field), perspective, and approach to KM. Moreover, this paradigm brings a theory of language into play. The origins and some of the contributions of discursive psychology are discussed, along with those from the wider field of discourse analysis. What could an approach grounded in discursive psychology bring to the study and practice of KM? Moreover, could discursive psychology provide the means to develop, evaluate, and analyze the knowledge sharing thematic categories introduced at the end of the previous chapter?

FURTHER READING

  1. Chalmers, A. (1999). What is this thing called Science? 3rd Edn. Maidenhead: Open University Press.
  2. Choo, C. and Bontis, N. (Eds). (2002). The Strategic Management of Intellectual Capital and Organizational Knowledge. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  3. Duguid, P. (2005). The art of knowing: social and tacit dimensions of knowledge and the limits of the community of practice. The Information Society, 21: 109–118.
  4. Heisig, P. (2009). Harmonisation of knowledge management—comparing 160 KM frameworks around the globe. Journal of Knowledge Management, 13, (4): 4–31.
  5. Ichijo, K. and Nonaka, I. (Eds). (2007). Knowledge Creation and Management: New Challenges for Managers. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  6. Ragab, M. and Arisha, A. (2013). Knowledge management and measurement: a critical review. Journal of Knowledge Management, 17, (6): 873–901.

Note

..................Content has been hidden....................

You can't read the all page of ebook, please click here login for view all page.
Reset
3.147.48.244