9
Critiquing and renewing the entrepreneurial imagination

Neil A. Thompson

Introduction

Few concepts in the history of entrepreneurial thought rival that of the entrepreneurial imagination. Imagination has been referenced in entrepreneurship’s early development from heterodox economics literature and continues to be cited in the present (Cornelissen, 2013; Gartner, 2007; Sarasvathy, 2002; Thompson, 2017; Witt, 2007). It has long been evoked to explain the creation of products, creative action, sensemaking of futures and pasts and decision making (Schumpeter, 1934; Shackle, 1979). There is an indication, however, that imagination is beginning to fall from grace in the cognitive domain of entrepreneurship studies. As Grégoire, Corbett, and McMullen’s (2011) review demonstrates, during the last decade entrepreneurial cognition research has largely examined cognitive resources (e.g. heuristic, effectual or causal modes of decision-making, mindful alertness, emotional energy, ambiguity absorption), perceptual processes (motivations, content and structure of cognitive maps, mental prototyping, incongruence and incompleteness of representations, cognitive frames), and expertise (prior knowledge, information processing) with scant empirical references to imagination. Where references to imagination do still exist, it is often immediately surpassed by reference to social psychological concepts – such as perspective taking (McMullen, 2010), inferential reasoning (Cornelissen, 2013), or counter-factual thinking. What is more, scholars across many disciplines (Daston, 1998), with entrepreneurship being no exception (Hjorth, 2007; Hjorth, Jones, & Gartner, 2008; Hsieh, Nickerson, & Zenger, 2007), have expressed an uneasiness with a concept that can be all too easily related to fetishizing or fantasizing – something unruly that needs to be suppressed once entrepreneurial ideas have formed and exploitation begins.

Given the extent to which entrepreneurial imagination is referenced in the history of entrepreneurship thought, and its possible fall from grace, it is surprising that it has thus far escaped from being a focal point of a critical review. Few entrepreneurship scholars have interrogated the concept and even fewer have undertaken the difficult task of theorizing upon the entrepreneurial imagination directly. As a consequence, there remains a rich opportunity to revisit the various fundamental assumptions of the entrepreneurial imagination. The purpose of this chapter is thus twofold: first, I critically examine current assumptions about the entrepreneurial imagination to pinpoint underlying philosophical assumptions, and, second, I renew theorizing in light of the burgeoning philosophy of imagination literature.

This chapter begins with a rendition of past and present conceptualizations of the entrepreneurial imagination upon which scholars base their claims. I base my critical review upon three alternative social ontologies making headway in entrepreneurship studies – processual, relationality and aesthetics. The results of my critique suggest that imagination is: a continuous process used to form perceptions of (alternative) realities (processual critique); a shared phenomenon that is socially situated and contingent upon social interaction (relational critique); and is reality-oriented through sensory perception (aesthetic critique). Following this argumentation, I renew theorizing upon the entrepreneurial imagination using an up-to-date collection of philosophical works, building from philosopher Mary Warnock (1978, 1994) as a central reference point (herself building on foundations of Romanticism, phenomenology and existentialism). Imagination is recast in terms of its primary and secondary modes that produces, situates and shares images within ongoing social practices (Gartner, Stam, Thompson, & Verduijn, 2016; Thompson, 2017). The chapter ends with a discussion about the relevance of entrepreneurial imagination for future entrepreneurship scholarship. In particular, I make the argument that a ‘return to imagination’ in cognitive-oriented research will help further growing aims of situating, embedding and embodying entrepreneurial cognition. In particular, I argue that re-incorporating imagination moves discussions of situated cognition from exclusively reflexivity and towards generative capacities of the mind, whilst still emphasizing mystery, doubt and possibility that underlie all entrepreneurial endeavours.

Revisiting the entrepreneurial imagination: three critiques

It is hard to understate the extent to which imagination and entrepreneurship have been intertwined, both in the academy and in popular culture. The aim of this portion of the chapter is to take a rare critical eye of entrepreneurial imagination to understand the common conceptualizations and assumptions. In doing so, however, I do not execute a systematic literature review, rather I touch upon the persistent and central ideas that scholars today reference when they evoke entrepreneurial imagination. In Section 1, I give a brief historical sketch of the entrepreneurial imagination and its connection to contemporary references. Section 2 builds a critique of these common conceptualizations along processual, relational and aesthetic grounds, which motivates my re-theorizing of entrepreneurial imagination in the subsequent Section 3.

Imagination in entrepreneurship studies

Early heterodox economic scholars regarded images and imagination as critical contributors to visualization and realization of entrepreneurial opportunities, decision making and the creation of new organizations. In this lineage of early work, perhaps the most well-known is Schumpeter (1934), who emphasized imagination as an activity through which entrepreneurs articulate new concepts and metaphors to grasp meaning and instigate change economies. In his view, imagination allows one to put oneself in the place of another person’s motives (or sentiments). Thus, the imagination is a vehicle of social change, as articulated in his notion of creative destruction. Schumpeter (1934, p. 86 emphasis added) writes, ‘a new and another kind of effort of will is therefore necessary in order to wrest, amidst the work and care of the daily round, scope and time for conceiving and working out the new combination and to bring oneself to look upon it as a real possibility and not merely as a day-dream’. In a similar vein, Shackle (1979) and Buchanan and Vanberg (1991) argue that uncertainty is at the root of all future expectations since ‘we can choose only what is still unactualized; we can choose amongst imaginations and figments. Imagined actions and policies can have only imagined consequences, and it follows that we can choose only an action whose consequences we cannot directly know, since we cannot be eyewitnesses of them because they are events in the future’ (Shackle, 1968). The principle of uncertainty provides entrepreneurs (and all humans) a cognitive opening to develop hitherto unexplored visions of the future, such that entrepreneurial choice and decision making is intertwined ‘amongst imagined experiences’ (Shackle, 1964, p. 12).

Another influential theorist, Kirzner (1973), is often thought of as standing in opposition to Schumpeterian and Shacklean views of imagination (Alvarez & Barney, 2007). And yet, while it is true that Kirzner initially had little reference to the imagination in his theory of arbitrage opportunities – i.e. they are confined to error recognition abilities (a single-period market decision) – he later professed that entrepreneurship in conditions of uncertainty involves multi-period market decisions that require ‘a more accurately envisaged future’ (Kirzner, 1982, p. 150). In fleshing out his well-known concept of “alertness” he claims ‘the human agent is at all times spontaneously on the lookout for hitherto unnoticed features of the environment (present or future), which might inspire new activity on his part’ such that entrepreneurial imagination ‘consists in seeing through the fog created by the uncertainty of the future’ (Kirzner, 1997, p. 51). Kirzner (1999) himself outlined how his theory is not necessarily inconsistent with a Schumpeterian perspective, arguing that both views stress that ‘it is [the entrepreneur’s] ability to shoulder uncertainty aside through recognizing opportunities in which imagination, judgement and creativity can successfully manifest themselves’ (Kirzner, 1998, p. 109). Finally, Lachmann (1986) makes the claim that markets are the outward manifestation of an endless stream of information continuously converted into new knowledge and new expectations. In his perspective, the forward-looking entrepreneurial imagination is the central mechanism from which new combinations of knowledge are derived.

Contemporary entrepreneurship research has kept the notion of imagination alive by reference to it as driving an individual ability to envision opportunities and reconceive of existing social order. Gartner (2007, p. 624) argues that the entrepreneurial imagination is the ‘generation of hypotheses about how the world might be, look and act’. Many contemporary scholars follow suit by arguing entrepreneurs use their imaginations to envision and recognize opportunities (Baron, 2006; Bjerke & Ramo, 2011; Cornelissen & Clarke, 2010; Davidsson, 2015; Hjorth, 2013; Klein, 2008; Sarasvathy, 2003; Witt, 2007). Foss and Foss (2008) note that while experiential knowledge is fundamental in the initial phase of venture formation, entrepreneurs may only be able to identify some elements of an opportunity, so they need to invoke imagination and search for and process information in order to more fully identify and evaluate the opportunity. Similarly, Cornelissen (2013, p. 704) contends that imagination seems to fuel the emotions and guide the inferential reasoning of entrepreneurs, allowing them to spot or create new opportunities by ‘blending different sets of ideas into a single guiding image, which, in turn, may trigger all sorts of inferential leaps’. Sarasvathy (2002) is a proponent of imagination such that entrepreneurs bring imagination into economic processes by sculpting visions and enacting the world they would want to live in. With this principle in mind, she emphasizes the urgent need to integrate imagination into economic theory (see Bronk (2009) for such an attempt).

Three critiques of the entrepreneurial imagination

In this section, I take a long overdue critical eye of such conceptualizations of the entrepreneurial imagination to develop a three-pronged critique – processual, relational and aesthetic.

The processual critique challenges contemporary conceptions of the entrepreneurial imagination as a cognitive ability associated mainly with the recognition of opportunities. In contemporary literature, imagination is commonly perceived to be operant in nascent ideation and early problem-solving stage of the entrepreneurship process (see Zhuo, 2008). While the imagination may be important for combining knowledge to come up with new venture ideas (Davidsson, 2015) or to envisage opportunities (Gartner, 2007), it is thought to give way to alternative cognitive processes (convergent, causal, effectual, inferential or analytical thinking) that are more necessary in the phases of opportunity evaluation and exploitation (Grégoire, Barr, & Shepherd, 2010). However, confining the imagination to a (bracketed) phase of the entrepreneurial process contradicts early theorists’ argumentation that all entrepreneurial decision-making – whether a decision to engage in entrepreneurial activities, attempt to acquire investment capital or target a particular customer group – involves imagining likely scenarios and sentiments of others under conditions of uncertainty. In line with processual perspective of entrepreneuring (Hjorth, Holt, & Steyaert, 2015; Verduyn, 2015), imagination is continuous and ever-present, with the resulting multiplicity of images (what one imagines) under constant reproduction and change throughout daily entrepreneurial life (Dimov, 2007). Entrepreneurial imagination is in constant use; thus, it is not restricted to ideation or opportunity recognition phases. For example, Popp and Holt (2012) build an argument for entrepreneurship as an unfolding imaginative process embedded in social contexts. The authors illustrate the emergence of entrepreneurship as a revelatory ‘poetic power’ that comes into being through the imaginative act of ‘making present’ – bringing forward that which is not yet present (see also Chiles, Elias, Vultee, & Zarankin, 2013; Dolmans, van Burg, Reymen, & Romme, 2014). Accordingly, a processual view of the entrepreneurial imagination challenges the common assumption that imagination can be contained to one (early) phase of the entrepreneurship process.

The second critique takes aim at the assumption that the entrepreneurial imagination is confined to an individual entrepreneur’s head. Being a fundamentally distinctive cognitive process, imagination is commonly referenced as an exercise of free will or unobstructed (cognitive) agency. However, a growing relational ontology of entrepreneurship has successfully criticized the presumption that the individual mind and the social world are ontologically and analytically two separate units that may interact without affecting their distinctiveness (Bradbury & Lichtenstein, 2000; Fletcher, 2006; Mutch, Delbridge, & Ventresca, 2006). As such, a relational critique uproots the presupposition that individual imaginative minds are the locus of creative ideas and opportunities. Instead, entrepreneurial imagination is a socially emergent and situated phenomenon in which the successive words and actions of others alters the nature and content of each participant’s imagining. A relational critique, therefore, claims that individualist conceptions of the entrepreneurial imagination understate the fact that the human mind is interdependent upon social relations, narratives and discourses. In other words, imagining is inseparable from the collaborative entrepreneurial process arising from shared activities, or practices (Schatzki, 2006), in which entrepreneurs imagine together with clients, suppliers, investors, etc. changes to objects and practices in a context of uncertainty. This resonates with Ramoglou and Tsang’s (2016) arguments that entrepreneurs use imagining within social contexts to formulate projections of possibly real, yet empirically ‘unactualised propensities’. Consequently, defining the entrepreneurial imagination as an individual cognitive process belies the notion that imagination both shapes as well as is shaped by others over the course of interaction.

The final critique pushes back against the tendency to view the entrepreneurial imagination as removed from or opposed to material realism. Much, if not all, of past and contemporary conceptualizations of the entrepreneurial imagination have strong undercurrents of subjectivism and idealism, whereupon which the social world exists as a matter of subjective perception and, as such, all changes to the social world originates from entrepreneurial visions. For example, the products of imagination, images, are thought to form the plan from which an enterprise emerges, thus it is an image, not the ontological phenomena they may reflect, that shapes entrepreneurial behaviour. This ‘subjectivist logic’, however, reinforces a tendency to view the entrepreneurial imagination as insensitive to or removed from socio-material realities. Alternatively, an aesthetic critique of the entrepreneurial imagination foremost draws attention to the absence of the senses – seeing, hearing, feeling, tasting and smelling – and their importance in grounding cognitive activities in actions and materiality. From an aesthetic tradition, cognitive and bodily ways of knowing and thinking about the world are not distinct phenomena but essentially intertwined (Strati, 2007), responsible for provoking the emotions and creative actions of entrepreneurs (Hjorth & Steyaert, 2008; Linstead & Hopfl, 2004). For example, the imagination of a restaurateur-entrepreneur is bound to the important dimensions of smell, sound, touch and sight of (imagined) cuisine, and the subconscious passion that can emerge from them. This is a notion that is underdeveloped in current literature leaving an untapped, rich opportunity to theorize how the interconnectedness of body and mind are shaping and shaped by entrepreneurs as they pursue endeavours.

In conclusion, processual, relational and aesthetic ontological orientations of the study of entrepreneurship largely undermine contemporary notions of the entrepreneurial imagination. Cornelissen (2013, p. 707) argues that the ‘singular focus on the static, condensed simultaneity of a single thought or symbol’ should give way to ‘study the plastic, dynamic nature of imagery and imagination and how emergent inferences, in turn, are realized within the institutional, technological, and economic constraints of a market or industry’. However, few researchers to date have heeded this call. There is a pressing need to renew connections to philosophy of imagination to develop these notions of entrepreneurial imagination in light of these criticisms. This oversight is surprising considering many entrepreneurship scholars proclaim the imagination as important while, on the other hand, the philosophy of imagination remains a rich and burgeoning area of study (see Kind, 2016). In the next section, I turn to and utilize the philosophy of imagination literature in order to address difficult questions related to the ontology of images and imagining.

Towards a renewed theory of the entrepreneurial imagination

The philosophy of imagination literature is an active area of philosophy exploring questions related to the nature of imagination; its relation to mental imagery, reasoning, learning, perception, memory, and dreaming; its role in creativity and the creation of music, art and fiction; and its implications for morality amongst others. While there is ongoing debate and there are various perspectives of the imagination, influential philosophers such as Mary Warnock (1978) conclude that the concept plays a much more fundamental in human life than commonly perceived. In this section, I review the notions of primary and secondary imagination, images and creative expression from this literature (for more complete review see Thompson, 2017). In section 2, I integrate this theorizing with entrepreneurship studies to develop a renew theory of the entrepreneurial imagination.

Primary and secondary imaginations, images and creative expression

According to Warnock (1978), the imagination is best thought of as constituting two modes, primary and secondary, that operate together to form images. The primary imagination describes the fundamental ability to continuously and subconsciously blend and unify aspects of one’s sensory experience with memories to form instantaneous perceptions of the world (Engell, 1981). This mode of imagination essentially designates a provisional reconciliation of body and mind, wherein perceptions are the product of combinations of senses, emotions and memories. Importantly, sensory experiences and memories are wrought by social and material processes, received via the senses, which makes the primary imagination empirically and socially anchored. For example, real-time perception of certain objects (e.g. a computer) are laden with meanings (e.g. utility as a tool) that is possible through a combination of the senses (e.g. seeing, touching, and hearing the computer) and past experiences (e.g. memories of its use). Perceptions, therefore, are not solely based on past experience or knowledge, nor from immediate sensory experiences. Instead, it is the blending of senses and memories that forms perception. Accordingly, the active primary imagination subconsciously blends and constructs a more dynamic, open-ended and meaningful reality than that of sensory experience or memory alone (Warnock, 1978).

The secondary imagination is a continuation of the primary, but it is consciously and voluntarily activated. As a person activates their secondary imagination, they allow the functioning of the primary imagination to bring forth images of something not currently present. In other words, people use their secondary imagination to force the initial conditions of imagining, but let the rest of the imaginative exercise unfold without interference. For instance, to imagine a new entrée, a restaurateur-entrepreneur does not make herself imagine the exact details of the possible dish in question. Rather, having forced the initial conditions (i.e. she wishes to imagine a new dish), she allows the imagination to operate in primary mode (normally delegated only to perception) to create an image that can be accessed consciously. Left to itself, her primary imagination develops an image of an entrée not present but in a reality-oriented way. The secondary imagination can be, therefore, thought of as ‘perceiving in hypothetical mode’ (Murphy, 2004) relying on the same operation of the primary mode (blending memories and senses), only for perceiving that which is not present. Consequently, the secondary imagination is distinguished from fantasizing (or what Coleridge would call ‘fancy’) because it establishes a link between what is perceived to be ‘real’ or ‘true’ and that which is considered totally ‘fictive’ or ‘false’.

As mentioned, the ‘object’ of the interplay between primary and secondary imaginations are defined as images that themselves have unique ontological characteristics. First, images are characteristically fleeting in that they ‘dissipate’ when one stops activating secondary mode and/or being receptive to it (Casey, 1974). Second, images are also characteristically vague in that they do not communicate detail or exact likeness, like a photograph, rather they are suggestive of a certain essence or aesthetic ‘feel’ (Sartre, 1940), such as image-touch, image-taste, image-sound, image-sight and image-smell (Warnock, 1978). For instance, the restaurateur-entrepreneur evoking her secondary imagination senses in her mind’s eye the aesthetics of a possible new entrée (i.e. its taste, smell and visual appeal), rather than perceive of a picture of itself. Finally, to materialize images, people undertake creative acts – talking, gesturing, writing, dancing, drawing, painting and so on – in an effort to express and communicate their suggestive content. Crucially, creative expression provides the social link between images of one person to another, such that they inspire others to imagine and share their images, which has recursive implications for one another’s further imagining (Thompson, 2017). For example, the restaurateur-entrepreneur imagining a new entrée uses creative expressions (perhaps gestures, talk and sketches) to communicate to another person the content of the image (its imagined aesthetic taste, smell and look). This other person not only uses imagination in primary mode to understand these suggestive expressions, but can also use her own imagination in secondary mode (and subsequence creative expressions) to alter or edit this image. As a consequence, through interactive sequences of novel talk and actions, creative expressions make images publicly available, and thus shared phenomena.

Renewing the entrepreneurial imagination

As can be seen, the entrepreneurial imagination precludes assumptions of episodic, individual and purely cognitive elements. In this section, I reconsider imagination for entrepreneurship studies by way of an example between co-founders attempting to incorporate feedback from a client on a product design.

The entrepreneurial imagination begins, just like in all humans, with the primary imagination and one’s attempt to perceive the material and social world. Accordingly, interactions between the co-founders coincide with the use of primary imagination to subconsciously understand and consciously participate in various social practices. A meeting between the entrepreneurs, for example, has certain understandings of the purpose of a meeting (incorporate client feedback) and how and where meetings are carried out. From this common basis, the entrepreneurs each share a base perception of client feedback as well as their immediate social and material context (e.g. office space in specific locale). Now, suppose one of the entrepreneurs participating in the meeting wishes to deal with client feedback by rethinking the design of their prototype product. To do so, she may activate her secondary imagination, allowing the primary mode to form an image of some altered product design. This image does not exist as a detailed and completed image in her mind’s eye. Rather, it reflects her primary imagination’s blending of memories and senses in which images are more aesthetic than complete. Next, using creative expression, she attempts to communicate this image using gestures, talk, and other objects (like drawing on a whiteboard) with other co-founders in the room. These creative expressions have implications for the primary imagination of all participating entrepreneurs, as they sense visually and audibly the creative expression from the first entrepreneur. Hence, the primary imagination not only blends and fuses this new sensory input to form immediate perceptions, but allows for all participants of the meeting to also imagine, with some degree of difference, what the first entrepreneur is imagining.

As the meeting continues, each entrepreneur takes turns in actively imagining, communicating and refining an image of a new product design that was initially instigated by client feedback. At this point, the contributions of one entrepreneur in the production of an image are lost in the recursive flow of imagining and creative expression, such that a shared image emerges (manifest perhaps physically on a whiteboard, computer, paper, etc.). Hence, as the entrepreneurs jointly imagine and express images, they manipulate their bodies and materials to express and communicate images in ways that diverge from the routine enactment of social practices. This exposition of entrepreneurial imagination can be repeated in different and subsequent situations, for example, when the team of entrepreneurs redevelops a business model or presents to potential investors. In these subsequent scenarios, the entrepreneurs attempt to communicate to each other or to investors some future imagined scenarios, customer experiences or aesthetic qualities of their product design, using creative expressions to try and stimulate others to imagine in a similar way. This may entail further feedback from which the entrepreneurial team may renew their joint imagining.

Discussion

The notion of entrepreneurial imagination has a long tradition in the history of entrepreneurship studies. Nevertheless, few scholars have conducted a review of common assumptions. In this chapter, I critique the entrepreneurial imagination literature by adopting a processual, relational and aesthetic stance. My review concludes that the entrepreneurial imagination is by and large conceived of: as operant only for early ideation of opportunities; is an individual-level phenomenon; and is isolated as solely a subjective cognitive process. I build from the philosophy of imagination literature to rethink the entrepreneurial imagination, which has three main contributions to entrepreneurship studies.

First, I show the value of building a constructive dialogue between entrepreneurship studies and philosophy. In particular, engaging with the philosophy of imagination literature, which remains a burgeoning area of thought, helps to challenge some common ontological conceptions of the entrepreneurial imagination. I have shown that prior conceptualizations have isolated imagining as a solely individual cognitive process that is active only for ideation. These overarching assumptions leave little room for a more phenomenologically driven understanding of imagination, as it is developed in philosophy. Indeed, the entrepreneurial imagination as a concept to date reflects the methodological individualism prominent in the history of entrepreneurial thought (Drakopoulou Dodd & Anderson, 2007; Watson, 2013), additive with a radical subjectivist account of images, visions and opportunities. Turning towards philosophy has the value of challenging and uprooting these taken-for-granted accounts.

The second contribution of this chapter is addressing taken-for-granted assumptions by renewing theorizing upon entrepreneurial imagination. I argue that imagining is an ongoing, shared and reality-oriented phenomenon that is a central component of perception, as well as an ability to perceive in hypothetical mode. In particular, drawing from the work of Warnock (1978) and Thompson (2017), I argue that imagination has two fundamental modes, primary and secondary, which operation together to form images. Rather than fall back into idealism and subjectivism, this literature demonstrates that image production is socially and materially anchored. Moreover, I address the ontology of images to argue that they are not analogous to pictures in the mind, but are more fleeting, vague and attuned with aesthetic perceptions. As one takes creative expression to ‘materialize’ and share them with others, participants jointly imagine, communicate and share images that are manifest in new artefacts (e.g. business models, products, strategies, etc.). Using the secondary imagination, however, is a conscious decision. As Weick (2005) argues, entrepreneurs (like all people) who fail to imagine other people, possible situations and alternative designs fail to be open to change and uncertainty. And yet, imagination is almost exclusively seen as a positive category in entrepreneurship literature, where it is likely that exercising the imagination may lead to anxieties based upon imagined negative scenarios that have a (miscalculated) chance of occurring. Future research could make new gains by exploring this negative or nuanced role of imagination.

Third, this chapter makes a contribution to current entrepreneurship research by arguing for the renewed relevance of the entrepreneurial imagination. Dew, Grichnik, Mayer-Haug, Read, and Brinckmann (2015) argue that entrepreneurial cognition cannot be ‘boxed-in’ as a mental condition or state rather it is tied into actions and objects, embodied with the senses. Hence, it is not located in individuals’ heads, but is shaped by social, physical and/or cultural contexts. In this vein, I have renewed thinking about the entrepreneurial imagination by situating it in ongoing social practices, which includes sensory experience, bodily movement and memories. Hence, returning to imagination, using the conceptualization developed here, furthers growing aims of situating, embedding and embodying entrepreneurial cognition by attending to the human ability to both perceive of immediate situations as well as perceive of possible futures. Accordingly, imagination helps to further discussions of situated entrepreneurial cognition by highlighting this important generative capacity of the mind, without straying into radical subjectivism.

In conclusion, despite a long history of references to entrepreneurial imagination to explain a variety of phenomena, such as ideation, opportunities, decision-making and creative action, the concept remains surprisingly underdeveloped. My critical review argues that the entrepreneurial imagination remains rooted in its methodological individualism and radical subjectivist past, which has complicated it use in a growing body of research developing the notion of situated entrepreneurial cognition. By making a connection to the philosophy of imagination literature, I have outlined a processually, relationally and aesthetically sensitive conception of the entrepreneurial imagination. As a consequence, I have argued that returning to imagination will help to further situate entrepreneurial cognition by attending to the human ability to not only perceive of immediate situations but imagine that which does not yet exist.

References

Alvarez, S. A., & Barney, J. B. (2007). Discovery and creation: Alternative theories of entrepreneurial action. Strategic Entrepreneurship Journal, 1(November), 11–26. http://doi.org/10.1002/sej

Baron, R. (2006). Opportunity recognition as pattern recognition. Academy of Management Perspectives, 20, 104–120. http://doi.org/10.5465/AMP.2006.19873412

Bjerke, B., & Ramo, H. (2011). Entrepreneurial imagination: Time, timing, space and place in business action. Cheltenham, UK. Northampton, MA, USA: Edward Elgar Publishing Limited.

Bradbury, H., & Lichtenstein, B. B. (2000). Relationality in organizational research: Exploring the space between. Organization Science, 11(5), 551–564. http://doi.org/10.1287/orsc.11.5.551.15203

Bronk, R. (2009). The romantic economist. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Buchanan, J. M., & Vanberg, V. J. (1991). The market as a creative process. Economics & Philosophy, 7(2), 167–186.

Casey, E. S. (1974). Toward a phenomenology of imagination. Journal of the British Society for Phenomenology, 5(1), 3–19. http://doi.org/10.1080/00071773.1974.11006346

Chiles, T. H., Elias, S., Vultee, D., & Zarankin, T. G. (2013). The Kaleidic world of entrepreneurs: Developing and grounding a metaphor for creative imagination. Qualitative Research in Organizations and Management: An International Journal, 8(3), 276–307.

Cornelissen, J. P. (2013). Book reviews: Portrait of an entrepreneur: Vincent van Gogh, Steve Jobs, and the entrepreneurial imagination. Academy of Management Review, 38(4), 700–709.

Cornelissen, J. P., & Clarke, J. (2010). Imagining and rationalizing opportunities: Inductive reasoning and the creation and justification of new ventures. Academy of Management Review, 35(4), 539–557.

Daston, L. (1998). Fear and loathing of the imagination in science. Daedalus, 127(1), 73–95.

Davidsson, P. (2015). Entrepreneurial opportunities and the entrepreneurship nexus: A re-conceptualization. Journal of Business Venturing, 30(5), 674–695. http://doi.org/10.1016/j.jbusvent.2015.01.002

Dew, N., Grichnik, D., Mayer-Haug, K., Read, S., & Brinckmann, J. (2015). Situated entrepreneurial cognition. International Journal of Management Reviews, 17(2), 143–164. http://doi.org/10.1111/ijmr.12051

Dimov, D. (2007). Beyond the single-person, single-insight attribution in understanding entrepreneurial opportunities. Entrepreneurship Theory and Practice, 31(5), 713–731.

Dolmans, S. A. M., van Burg, E., Reymen, I. M. M. J., & Romme, A. G. L. (2014). Dynamics of resource slack and constraints: Resource positions in action. Organization Studies, 35(4), 511–549. http://doi.org/10.1177/0170840613517598

Drakopoulou Dodd, S., & Anderson, A. R. (2007). Mumpsimus and the mything of the individualistic entrepreneur. International Small Business Journal, 25(4), 341–360. http://doi.org/10.1177/0266242607078561

Engell, J. (1981). The creative imagination: Enlightenment to romanticism. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

Fletcher, D. E. (2006). Entrepreneurial processes and the social construction of opportunity. Entrepreneurship & Regional Development, 18(5), 421–440. http://doi.org/10.1080/08985620600861105

Foss, K., & Foss, N. (2008). Understanding opportunity discovery and sustainable advantage: The role of transaction costs and property rights. Strategic Entrepreneurship Journal, 2, 191–207.

Gartner, W. B. (2007). Entrepreneurial narrative and a science of the imagination. Journal of Business Venturing, 22(5), 613–627.

Gartner, W. B., Stam, A. M. C. E., Thompson, N. A., & Verduijn, J. K. (2016). Entrepreneurship as practice: Grounding contemporary practice theory into entrepreneurship studies. Entrepreneurship and Regional Development, 28(9–10), 813–816.

Grégoire, D. A., Barr, P. S., & Shepherd, D. (2010). Cognitive processes of opportunity recognition: The role of structural alignment. Organization Science, 21(2), 413–431. http://doi.org/10.1287/orsc.1090.0462

Grégoire, D. A., Corbett, A. C., & McMullen, J. S. (2011). The cognitive perspective in entrepreneurship: An agenda for future research. Journal of Management Studies, 48(6), 1443–1477. http://doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-6486.2010.00922.x

Hjorth, D. (2007). Lessons from Iago: Narrating the event of entrepreneurship. Journal of Business Venturing, 22(5), 712–732. http://doi.org/10.1016/j.jbusvent.2006.10.002

Hjorth, D. (2013). Absolutely fabulous! Fabulation and organisation-creation in processes of becoming-entrepreneur. Society and Business Review, 8(3), 205–224. http://doi.org/10.1108/SBR-02-2013-0020

Hjorth, D., Holt, R., & Steyaert, C. (2015). Entrepreneurship and process studies. International Small Business Journal, 33(6), 599–611. http://doi.org/10.1177/0266242615583566

Hjorth, D., Jones, C., & Gartner, W. B. (2008). Introduction for ‘recreating/recontextualising entrepreneurship’. Scandinavian Journal of Management, 24(2), 81–84. http://doi.org/10.1016/j.scaman.2008.03.003

Hjorth, D., & Steyaert, C. (2008). The politics and aesthetics of entrepreneurship. Cheltenham: Edward Elgar Publishing.

Hsieh, C., Nickerson, J. A., & Zenger, T. R. (2007). Opportunity discovery, problem solving and a theory of the entrepreneurial firm. Journal of Management Studies, 44(7), 1255–1277.

Kind, A. (2016). The Routledge handbook of philosophy of imagination. London, UK: Taylor & Francis.

Kirzner, I. M. (1973). Competition and entrepreneurship. Chicago: Chicago University Press.

Kirzner, I. M. (1982). Uncertainty, discovery and human action: A study of the entrepreneurial profile in the misesian system. In I. M. Kirzner (Ed.), Method, process and Austrian economics (pp. 139–160). Washington, DC: Heath.

Kirzner, I. M. (1997). Entrepreneurial discovery and the competitive market process: An Austrian approach. Journal of Economic Literature, 35(1), 60–85.

Kirzner, I. M. (1998). Entrepreneurship. In P. J. Boettke (Ed.), The Elgar companion to Austrian economics. Cheltenham, UK; Northampton, MA, USA: Edward Elgar Publishing, Incorporated.

Kirzner, I. M. (1999). Creativity and/or alertness: A reconsideration of the Schumpeterian entrepreneur. The Review of Austrian Economics, 11(1), 5–17. http://doi.org/10.1023/A:1007719905868

Klein, P. (2008). Opportunity discovery, entrepreneurial action and economic organization. Strategic Entrepreneurship Journal, 2, 175–190.

Lachmann, L. M. (1986). The market as an economic process. Boston, MA, USA : Wiley-Blackwell.

Linstead, S., & Hopfl, H. (2004). The aesthetics of organization. London: Sage.

McMullen, J. S. (2010). Perspective taking and the heterogeneity of the entrepreneurial imagination. In R. Koppl, S. Horwitz, P. Desrochers (Eds.), What is so Austrian about Austrian economics? (Vol. 14, pp. 113–143). Bingley, UK: Emerald Group Publishing Limited. http://doi.org/doi:10.1108/S1529-2134(2010)0000014009

Murphy, K. M. (2004). Imagination as joint activity: The case of architectural interaction. Mind, Culture, and Activity, 11(4), 267–278. http://doi.org/10.1207/s15327884mca1104_3

Mutch, A., Delbridge, R., & Ventresca, M. (2006). Situating organizational action: The relational sociology of organizations. Organization, 13(5), 607–625. http://doi.org/10.1177/1350508406067006

Popp, A., & Holt, R. (2012). The presence of entrepreneurial opportunity. Business History, 55(July 2015), 1–20. http://doi.org/10.1080/00076791.2012.687539

Ramoglou, S., & Tsang, E. W. K. (2016). A realist perspective of entrepreneurship: Opportunities as propensities. Academy of Management Review, 41(3), 410–434. http://doi.org/10.5465/amr.2014.0281

Sarasvathy, S. D. (2002). Entrepreneurship as economics with imagination. Business Ethics Quaterly, 3, 95–112. http://doi.org/10.5840/ruffinx200238

Sarasvathy, S. D. (2003). Entrepreneurship as a science of the artificial. Journal of Economic Psychology, 24, 203–220. http://doi.org/10.1016/S0167-4870(02)00203-9

Sartre, J.-P. (1940). L’Imaginaire: Psychologie phénoménologique de l’imagination. Paris: Gallimard.

Schatzki, T. R. (2006). On organizations as they happen. Organization Studies, 27(12), 1863–1873.

Schumpeter, J. A. (1934). The theory of economic development. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

Shackle, G. L. S. (1964). General thought-schemes and the economist. Edited by E. Woolwich. London: Woolwich Polycentric Press.

Shackle, G. L. S. (1968). Expectations, investment, and income (2nd ed.). Oxford: Clarendon Press.

Shackle, G. L. S. (1979). Imagination and the nature of choice. Edinburgh, UK: Edinburgh University Press.

Strati, A. (2007). Sensible knowledge and practice-based learning. Management Learning, 38(1), 61–77. http://doi.org/10.1177/1350507607073023

Thompson, N. A. (2017). Imagination and creativity in organizations. Organization Studies, in press.

Verduyn, K. (2015). Entrepreneuring and process: A Lefebvrian perspective. International Small Business Journal, 33(6), 638–648. http://doi.org/10.1177/0266242614559059

Warnock, M. (1978). Imagination. Berkeley, CA: University of California Press.

Warnock, M. (1994). Imagination and time. Oxford, UK; Cambridge, MA, USA : Wiley.

Watson, T. J. (2013). Entrepreneurial action and the Euro-American social science tradition: Pragmatism, realism and looking beyond ‘the entrepreneur’. Entrepreneurship & Regional Development, 25(1–2), 16–33. http://doi.org/10.1080/08985626.2012.754267

Weick, K. E. (2005). Organizing and failures of imagination. International Public Management Journal, 8(3), 425–438. http://doi.org/10.1080/10967490500439883

Witt, U. (2007). Firms as realizations of entrepreneurial visions. Journal of Management Studies, 44(7), 1125–1140.

Zhuo, J. (2008). New look at creativity in the entrepreneurial process. Strategic Entrepreneurship Journal, 2, 1–5.

..................Content has been hidden....................

You can't read the all page of ebook, please click here login for view all page.
Reset
3.137.180.113