p.343

20

Money and finance

Ethical considerations

Antonio Argandoña

Financial institutions and markets render vital services to the economy: they provide funds for consumption and investment, they facilitate access to payment systems, offer custom-designed risk-return combinations for asset management, and manifest an outstanding capacity for innovation in products and services, among many other virtues. Finance is concerned with money, credit, assets, debt, risk, banks, investment, and a variety of investment funds, but it goes further than that: “financing an activity really is creating the architecture for reaching our goals, and providing stewardship afterwards to protect and conserve the achievement of that goal” (Shiller 2012: 6). So finance has a social and moral significance. But it also has its dark side: it is often accused of being cold and even heartless, its managers sometimes prove willing to shade the truth and take whatever advantage lies open to them, and the apparent concentration of power in major financial institutions may work to the detriment of those without enough power or wealth.

But this is nothing new. Since ancient times people have criticized usury (charging abusive interest on loans), worried about the power of owners of capital, and fretted over the ways in which money and wealth elicit greed and profligacy (on medieval usury, see Munro 2003). Finance creates opportunities for huge profits, sometimes at the expense of other people, or undertakes excessive risks whose unraveling can ruin families and companies. In recent years, the criticisms have become stronger, particularly after the financial crisis of 2008,1 not to mention the manipulation of Libor and exchange rates, bankers’ collusion in money laundering and tax evasion operations, or the supposed capture of legislators and regulators by the bankers’ lobby. So there are many reasons to undertake an ethical reflection on finance.

Financial ethics is the body of principles, norms and virtues that guide the behavior of financial agents and organizations towards goals that are not only efficient and profitable, but also good, fair or proper. From the economic viewpoint, people make financial decisions based primarily on their preferences and a set of constraints (resources, relative prices and costs, regulations). Ethics is not one restriction imposed from outside, but an essential component of profitable and responsible decisions. Ethical principles (honesty, integrity, justice, truthfulness, prudence, responsibility, stewardship, accountability and many others) are common to all decisions, and they are not different from those of general ethics, but their content and application must take into account the specific circumstances of each case (Argandoña 1995b). For example, fairness is required of a judge, not to mention a sports referee, as well as an account manager with a fiduciary duty towards his client or a broker who sells a standard bond to an unknown customer. In each of these instances, fairness is required but the contents of that virtue will be different in each type of case (see Heath 2010 on fairness in finance).

p.344

The ethical analysis of financial decisions arises from the theories and principles of philosophical or religious ethics, but these decisions cannot be analyzed in isolation from some exogenous variables. One of these is the set of ideas and values shared in the community that influences people’s attitudes: many shortcomings of financial institutions and markets reflect the social environment. For example, if citizens show an individualistic and selfish character, those working in finance will show similar moral biases.

Another relevant variable when judging financial ethics is the set of theories that provide a rationale for financial practices (Mackenzie 2008). These theories share with economics the goal of efficiency, along with some basic assumptions, such as a narrow conception of rationality, the identification of good with the maximization of wealth, an instrumentalist interpretation of science and an alleged ethical neutrality (Ryan et al. 2010). Financial models are considered ethically neutral, but the assumptions underlying them imply conceptions of the person and society, their motivations and behaviors, and these have ethical implications. The criticisms that some theories have received during the recent crisis were due not only to technical faults, but to the alleged promotion of immoral behavior from within the models (Dembinski 2009).

In this chapter we outline the ethical issues raised by modern finance. In the first section we delineate the legal and institutional framework of the system. In a longer second section we consider the roles of financial intermediaries, such as banks and investment vehicles, noting in addition particular questions that arise with specific financial instruments (such as derivatives), along with issues related to risk. A third section broaches two practices of financial markets, speculation and high-frequency trading. In the fourth section we introduce, briefly, some alternative models of finance.

The legal and institutional framework

Financial markets and intermediaries operate within a legal and institutional framework that determines how costs, benefits, and risks are shared among the parties. This framework includes external institutions such as the rule of law, property, contract legislation, and a national currency established by a central bank. Along with supervisory institutions, regulations, and crisis management procedures internal to each bank, this framework both undergirds and creates ethical obligations.

Although legality does not mean morality, for law and ethics pursue different goals, there is nonetheless a relationship between ethics and regulation (Davies 2001; Kane 2014). In some instances, high ethical standards may make some regulations redundant: ethics substitute for regulation. However, it is more common for them to be complementary: ethics goes beyond the law and addresses problems that the law must not be concerned with, because they involve people’s conscience (including inner attitudes or values) or their personal discretion. However, in other cases, ethics may demand more than the law either because there are circumstances that the law cannot consider or because there exist supererogatory duties that the law should not command. Finally, there are many examples of situations in which a regulation (or a change in regulation) would not only affect risks and returns but promote, even unintentionally, immoral behavior (Koehn 2010).

Regulations may create ethical obligations for those who are bound by them: if they are not unnecessary, arbitrary or unfair, regulations and laws must be obeyed, even if they are imperfect or impose unreasonable costs on agents. But regulations may also create perverse incentives or moral hazards (for example, when one bank takes more risk because the taxpayers, not the shareholders, will bear the burden of rescue in case of a crisis), or opportunities for rent seeking (the grant of legal advantages to some entities at the expense of others or of all citizens, as summarized in Tollison 2012).

p.345

There are also ethical duties regarding the basic framework of finance, including a general duty to maintain the proper legal and regulatory framework suitable for a free and decent society. More specific obligations might include drawing up a standard concerning banks’ equity or creating a deposit insurance institution; such endeavors have ethical content in so far as they bear important consequences for citizens’ welfare and condition their behavior.

Money is an important component of the economic system’s legal and institutional framework. The word “money” has several different meanings: it may refer to a means of payment, or to income, wealth, or power, or it may suggest a cause of happiness, among other meanings. Given these senses, money may serve either as a means or an end. In a narrow sense, it refers to currency, the means used to make payments and to facilitate exchange. In this sense money serves a social function: it is liquidity, universal purchasing power, a means for achieving disparate ends; as such, money is also a creator of opportunities, allowing people to exercise individual freedom and collaborate impersonally in other people’s projects.

As a means of exchange, it is better to have more money than less. However, money is more than a tool: it represents wealth, power, prestige, and security. Money is a motivator for many actions, at least in the sense that it represents the power to acquire things or attain a status. And in some instances, not necessarily the best, the desire for money may constitute the end itself.

As a means of payment and a store of value money plays a key role in the lives of people, so the ethical principles of ownership should be applied to it. Moreover, money is based on trust: we accept coins, notes and deposits as money because other people also accept them. Trust in money is built on three pillars, one institutional and legal, one based on trust in banks, and another that relies on the stability of its purchasing power.

The legal framework of money includes legislation on currency counterfeiting, public guarantees on deposits, mechanisms for preventing bank crises and other policies and structures. Trust in banks is necessary because they play a prominent role in the money creation process.2 But confidence in banks is subject to limitations: they only keep a very small part of their deposits in a liquid form (fractional reserve banking),3 which sometimes makes them unable to reimburse those deposits, and they also keep only a small part of their assets as shareholders’ equity, which may raise a risk of insolvency. This may cause losses to depositors, blockages in the payment system and paralysis of financing mechanisms in the economy, destroying trust.

Finally, the use of money as a means of exchange is based on the expectation that its purchasing power will be stable, that is, the inflation rate will be low. Inflation causes many economic and ethical harms: it leads to unfair income and wealth distribution, it is a non-democratic and unfair tax on currency, and it generates inefficiencies that may lead to a deterioration of citizens’ standard of living. There has been a general agreement among economists that, in the medium and long term, inflation is caused by excessive growth of the quantity of money; controlling this process is the job of monetary policy, which is implemented by the central bank.

Originally, money is a spontaneous non-state creation, as explained by Hayek (1976) and others (Lietaer and Lunne 2013). This spontaneity is seen in many developments that have taken place in recent decades. Here we will mention only three: e-money, private and social currencies, and virtual monies.

E-monies (PayPal, Apple Pay, Google Wallet and many others) are means of payment of limited acceptance, bereft of any legal backing, and a form of mobile money. Various types of social, community or cooperative currencies have been developed by retail associations or local governments in several countries, often with a social purpose, such as providing credit to local companies, fostering proximity of trade and consumption or encouraging fair trade (for example, the Swiss Wir that has been operating since the 1930s, the Wörgl in Austria, or the Bristol Pound in Great Britain). Digital currencies have also flourished; the best known is the Bitcoin, a virtual international currency exchanged by digital means and not backed by any government but by a person-to-person network of users.

p.346

The questions that ethics raises about these currencies are similar to those it asks about traditional currencies: What is their social function (their contribution to the life and the economy of citizens)? Do they create excessive or poorly understood risks that prove difficult to hedge against (counterfeiting, inflation or depreciation)? Are they used for permissible or ethical ends (as opposed to fraudulent or illicit purposes)? And what is the basis of the trust that underlies their use? It is not enough that a currency fulfills a social function to be accepted as ethically correct (see Angel and McCabe 2014).

The ethics of financial intermediaries

The financial system is the set of markets and institutions that make up financial activities. Its social function is to efficiently satisfy the needs of the suppliers and demanders of funds, namely to allocate savings in profitable controlled-risk investments; to finance consumption, production or investment projects; to provide means of payment for the economy, and to manage and control risk. The fulfilment of these tasks gives legitimacy to the system and translates into ethical responsibilities for all the agents.

There are many varieties of financial institutions, but all have some common characteristics: they all operate within a network of institutions and markets and each receives funds from clients (creditors) and lends them to other clients (debtors), thereby incurring risk but also the potential for profit. This simple explanation allows us to identify three areas of ethical responsibilities common to all institutions: duties to their customers, duties to other actors, and internal duties of governance (management and control).

The main principle in the relationships of banks with their customers is that the interest of the latter must take precedence over the interest of the first. Their professional relationships are based on contracts that should be governed by principles of justice or fairness, which entails that both parties must comply with the terms of the contract (see Koehn 1994). In finance those contracts have usually non-explicit terms, such as shared interests (both parties expect to gain from the relationship), mutual respect and impartiality (equitable treatment of different customers) and reciprocity (the relationship may be repeated in the future, as discussed in Johnson 2015).

Financial institutions have more complete information about their products (and their risks) than do their clients and may use this asymmetric information for their own benefit at the expense of the clients’ interests. This entails the obligation of providing the customers with the full, fair, accurate, complete, objective, relevant, timely and understandable information they need to make rational decisions,4 as well as negative obligations such as avoiding misrepresentation, confusion or concealment of important information, fraud, manipulation, price-rigging, insider trading,5 conflicts of interest and other practices. Another moral duty refers to the appropriate use of sensitive (and confidential) information about the customer.

Financial intermediaries often have greater power than their clients and can abuse that power, not respecting the other party’s freedom to choose, contract, undertake and exchange. Abuse of power may take place when drafting the contract but also in performing it: for example, the right to monitor the borrower to ensure the return of credit does not entitle the bank to interfere unduly in the debtor’s business, and the emergence of difficulties in paying back the loan does not allow undue harshness against a defaulting client. Procedural justice demands equitable, but not necessarily equal, treatment of its various customers.

p.347

Some financial institutions have special duties to specific clients. For example, commercial banks must safeguard and diligently manage their deposit holders’ funds and provide services of liquidity management. Banks’ obligations related to their lending activities include the honest examination of applications, prudent decision-making in granting loans (fairness in setting interest rates, charges, installments, guarantees, collateral, etc.), monitoring the borrower and fair treatment in the event of default.

In a highly interconnected world, the actions of a financial institution can have negative impacts on many others—or, with a positive language, they should cooperate for the common good of the industry; for example, poor management of liquidity or solvency in one bank can cause a general panic that endangers others. Problems may occur if all banks adopt the same models of analysis that meet rational criteria when applied to one institution, but whose application may generate a uniform but unmerited risk in other banks, i.e., a systemic risk. Other forms of harm occur when a bank seeks a special regulatory treatment that may be unfair to competitors and may allow the exploitation of clients; or practices regulatory arbitrage (taking advantage of locations where regulations are more lax) compromising the system’s stability; or obstructs the orderly functioning of the markets impairing their social role as devices for the dissemination of information and the discovering of opportunities for all (Kleinau 2014).

These responsibilities towards other actors are important even when each institution is unable to understand all the consequences of its decisions on others; these responsibilities fall primarily on the supervisors, but this does not preclude holding the institution itself ethically responsible, especially when it is “too-big-to” or “too-connected-to” fail. Nevertheless, even if stability is a public good, it is not the only one; there are others, such as growth and innovation. A culture that fosters stability above all else may not be the best.

The ethical duties of banks to their customers and other entities turn ultimately into internal obligations for boards and managers. In general, financial crises draw justifiable attention to external shocks, but such crises also raise questions about failures in the management of incentives (conflicts of interest, remuneration schemes, agency problems), problems of information and control (transparency, risk management and supervision), and lapses in accounting (tampering with financial statements), among others. These problems point also to an information asymmetry between the bank’s shareholders and its managers, when the latter may obtain a short-term personal gain at the cost of long-term risks or losses for the organization.

The solution to these problems requires, at the organizational level, the establishment of good practices to avoid opportunism and conflicts of interest, and also a culture of high ethical standards. If agents have acquired solid virtues it will be easier for them to identify emerging ethical problems, assess their consequences, look for alternatives and take the best decision, and also develop the will to effectively implement it. Prudence or practical wisdom is probably “the banker’s characteristic virtue” (Termes 1995: 130); the second is justice or fairness, and it is accompanied by honesty, integrity, good faith, truthfulness, diligence or professionalism and accountability, among others. These virtues manifest themselves in everyday conduct and they reflect, more generally, a society in which there is trust. As a public good produced and enjoyed by all, trust depends also on institutional factors, including the rule of law, a fair judicial system, and a dependable framework of financial regulation.

p.348

Commercial banks, shadow banks, investment banks

Commercial banks are the financial intermediaries par excellence, so it is not surprising that there are important discussions of bank ethics in the literature (Cowton 2002; Green 1989; Koslowski 1995, 2011). Traditionally banks were financed by deposits, granted medium and long-term credit to households and companies, maintained close relationships with their customers and were integrated into their local communities. However, this model has undergone significant mutations in recent decades, due to innovations in products and processes, technological change (that, for example, expanded customers’ opportunities, encouraged greater appetite for risk, short-term outlook and less loyalty to banks), new means of payment (which might render obsolete one of the banks’ main functions) and deregulation (which opens up new opportunities for the other intermediaries and increases competition).

The reaction of many commercial banks to these changes has been to adapt their business models to those of their non-bank competitors, and this has also changed their principles and behavior. For example, securitization provided opportunities for obtaining finance by routes other than deposits and changed the banking model from “originate-to-hold” (hold the credit on its balance sheet until its due date) to “originate-to-distribute” (convert the credit into collateral for a security, sell it and take the risk off the balance sheet); the use of automated procedures for granting loans has weakened personal relationships, replacing, thereby, an ethos of service with a sales-driven culture.

As a result of these changes, the culture of many commercial banks has changed: they are financed impersonally in wholesale markets and lend impersonally through securities, use sophisticated risk models, pursue purely short-term financial targets and stop working with their local communities.

The term “shadow banking” does not imply any negative legal or moral judgment. It is used to designate those organizations (investment banks, brokerage houses, finance companies, structured investment vehicles and many others) that provide banking services to specific clients but neither receive deposits nor handle payment systems, which puts them outside of the official backstop system (the central bank as source of liquidity, along with deposit guarantee programs). They operate in a less regulated environment than commercial banks, though often are owned and managed by them, and have lower costs, substantial competitive advantages and opportunities for big profits (Poszar et al. 2013).

The ethical problems affecting shadow banking are similar to those of commercial banks, although more acute, because its business model is more aggressive, the risk level higher, the leverage greater, and the equity levels lower. Shadow banks are highly connected with other institutions, which may create systemic risk, and they may also be prone to problems related to opacity, herd behavior or conflict of interests.

Investment banks undertake a broad range of operations with other financial intermediaries and private customers: they help private companies obtain financing by means of public share offers; they trade with institutional investors on the secondary markets; they act as market makers, adding depth and liquidity to the market; they trade in derivatives; they facilitate transactions on the repo markets and provide clearing services to other financial institutions, and they also carry out operations on their own behalf. They are usually large organizations, with a considerable resource-generating capacity and a powerful influence on the economy.

Investment banks have often been criticized due to the risks they take and transmit to the rest of the system, the complexity of their products, the opacity of their operations and their interconnection with many markets and institutions, which leads to negative knock-on effects (Painter 2010; Reynolds and Newell 2011).

p.349

Investment funds, mutual funds, exchange-traded funds, hedge funds

Investment funds are collective investment institutions that hold portfolios containing only financial or real-estate assets; investors buy shares in these funds, thereby becoming co-owners of that portfolio.6 Mutual funds target modest investors who cannot manage their wealth personally and offer them diversified portfolios with yields that are higher than could be obtained on their own. Pension funds receive employees’ savings to provide them income when they retire. In exchange-traded funds investors buy and sell the fund’s shares on the stock market; their assets consist of participations in indexes; they are diversified products, easy to operate and with low costs.

The ethical problems that usually arise with respect to these funds include putting managers’ interests before that of clients’ (for example, a manager strategically executes his own trade prior to the request of a client), generating unnecessary trades (churning) to collect more commissions, or dealing unfairly with an investor. Excessive risk-taking is not frequent due to the strictness of regulations.7

Hedge funds have undergone rapid growth in recent years. They are usually large, have a small number of high net worth clients and impose strict terms on them, in particular for the withdrawal of funds. They operate under lax regulations, they are heavily leveraged, their strategies are opaque and they offer high yields with high risk. They charge high commissions and their managers also have other incentives tied to the fund’s performance.

Hedge funds came under strong criticism in the recent financial crisis for their size and power, aggressive strategies, high potential profits (and losses) and the risks they take or transfer to other participants. They were also criticized for the lack of transparency of their operations, although this is not relevant for the market’s efficiency when such information concerns the fund’s internal strategy and is accepted by its participants. Possible agency problems (putting the interests of the managers ahead of those of the customers) and conflicts of interest (for example, when managers carry out proprietary trading that can cause lower profits for clients) may also arise (see Donaldson 2010 on the ethical problems of hedge funds).

Financial derivatives and securitization

Derivatives are financial instruments in which an asset’s value depends on or is derived from the value of another underlying asset, index, or interest rate. There are many types of financial derivatives; the best known are forward contracts (buying or selling at a price fixed beforehand, with delivery at a specified time in the future), futures (the same operation with standardized products in organized markets), options (the right, but not the obligation, to buy or sell something at a given time in the future at a specified price) and swaps (two parties agree to swap financial instruments at a given time in the future at a specified price: for example, a contract at a fixed interest rate for another contract at a variable rate). Derivatives have been used for centuries to hedge risks: for example, farmers sell their harvest beforehand in the futures market at a fixed price to protect themselves against an eventual drop in prices.

Derivatives are morally legitimate products which, like many others, can be used inappropriately, becoming “toxic assets.”8 Sometimes they are viewed with mistrust, perhaps because their operation is not properly understood: for example, a future is a zero-sum contract, what one party wins the other party loses, but it enables the risk to be borne by the party who is best able to do so, with a compensation. Another reason for criticism is their speculative use and the potentially high risk: for example, when an option is financed with debt, the gain can be very high, but the loss, if it happens, could be also very high.

p.350

Securitization consists of pooling credits that form part of a financial institution’s assets (mortgages, auto loans or credit card-linked debt, for example), taking them out of its balance sheet and transferring them to a “special purpose vehicle” (SPV) to act as collateral for derivatives sold to investors. Securitization is a good technical and ethical practice, which allows financial institutions to transfer the risk to other investors, reduce their equity requirements and obtain liquidity to fund new operations. However, this practice can also be used in an imprudent way: for example, in the years of strong real-estate growth in the US, driven by low interest rates and policies promoting the extension of family homeownership, subprime loan originators, who were paid by the quantity and amount of loans granted, regardless of risk of default thereof, had an incentive to conceal the potential borrowers’ true risk, and even to encourage them to make misleading statements. Mortgage lenders were not diligent in controlling those risks because, via securitization, mortgages and risk would disappear from their balance sheet.

During placement of the collateralized debt obligations (CDOs) and other derivatives in the years before the financial crisis of 2008, basic rules of prudent investment were also disregarded, such as ascertaining the nature and scope of the risk. The rating agencies, which played a central role in the design and valuation of derivatives, committed big mistakes: the sophisticated criteria used were not appropriate, and conflicts of interest arose because the agency had to assess the products submitted to it by the same banks that had to pay their fees. The derivative portfolios’ risk was hedged by credit default swaps (CDSs), in which the issuer undertook to compensate the investor if the asset on which the contract was based lost value or defaulted, in exchange for a premium. Not only were they complex; the CDSs created the illusion that the hedged assets were secure, increasing their imprudent use.

Risk management

All financial transactions involve expectations about the future and therefore carry a risk. This risk may be understood both as hazard and opportunity: sometimes, it is worth accepting risk to get a higher return; other times, it is best to protect oneself from it, pass it on to someone else or, simply, avoid it. The goal of risk management is to prevent the losses that may occur in the future because of the risk and to ensure that the occurrence of critical events does not endanger the organization’s survival (see Boatright 2012 and Young 2010).

Risk is not just a technical issue but also an ethical one, because of its consequences on the agent’s welfare and on others, and it may even endanger the functioning of the financial system as a whole (systemic risk). A bank’s portfolio risk, for example, is borne not only by its shareholders but also by its creditors and even by other agents who act as counterparties in its operations, but decisions on these risks are frequently taken by the bank managers without considering the interests of other stakeholders.

The nature and level of risk must be known, identified, and evaluated in order to decide the best strategy: accept it (if, for example, the institution has enough capital buffer to cover the possible losses), or protect oneself against it (balancing the assets and liabilities, or monitoring borrowers, as the banks do, or passing on the risk through securitization, hedging with derivatives or taking out insurance). There are also immoral forms of risk transfer, by deceit, abuse of power, product opacity or creating moral hazard.

Prudence is the main virtue of the risk manager: excessive risk-taking may be an imprudent action, even if it does not lead immediately to losses. Currently, most regulators delegate an important part of risk control to the financial institution; this reduces the costs for the bank but does not lessen its responsibility, and may increase costs for others, including the taxpayers. Sound risk management (both technically and ethically) and the exercise of accountability contribute positively to the creation of trust.

p.351

Using complex mathematical models has made risk management easier, but it has also created new problems. Sometimes it has been forgotten that the results of these models are dependent on their underlying assumptions and on the information used to calibrate them. Decisions have been left to experts who do not always have the appropriate experience. Reliable models may create the illusion of safety and lead to excessive risk-taking; moreover, each manager sees only the part of the problem that affects him, so that the protection of his institution may be compatible with the creation of greater systemic risks. Finally, the widespread use of similar models based on the same assumptions may create situations of herd behavior, leading to excessive optimism during booms and panic during crashes.

The ethics of financial markets

Financial markets put buyers and sellers in contact with each other, either directly or through intermediaries (brokers, dealers, market makers). The main contribution of these markets to the welfare of society is setting prices and providing information to the market participants and to the society.

Sometimes it is argued that markets are unethical, due to the suspicion that the people who operate in them are moved by greed. But one should not confuse a legitimate personal interest with greed. Moreover, markets are only a means to achieve buyers’ and sellers’ goals; the morality of transactions depends on the goals of the agents and on the means used; if the parties operate in suitable conditions of freedom and access to information, both gain from the exchange and they contribute to efficient resource allocation.

The markets’ proper operation depends on a suitable legal and institutional framework that guarantees fair treatment and avoids manipulative, fraudulent, or misleading conduct. Fairness in financial markets is defined by a set of freedoms and rights: freedom from coercion, misrepresentation, and non-rational impulses, as well as rights to (roughly) equal information, intellectual processing power, bargaining power, as well as efficient prices (Shefrin and Statman 1993). The weight of these responsibilities falls upon regulators, but the participants’ duties cannot be ignored: for example, they must not commit fraud or deceit, or abuse a dominant position due to asymmetric information; they should not engage in opportunistic behavior when they can breach a contract with impunity; and they should take into account possible externalities that transfer to a third party the costs generated by the decision maker. Here we will discuss two typical problems of financial markets: Speculation and high frequency trading.

Speculation

Speculation is a routine practice on the financial markets.9 Strictly speaking, it is the purchase (or sale) of an asset without performing a simultaneous hedging operation, with the hope that its price will be higher (or lower) in the near future, while at the same time running the risk that the expectation may not be fulfilled. But often people call speculation, improperly, any operation involving buying low and selling high.

A grocery store does this, but its profit is often justified by the service rendered by providing consumers with the products they want. The moral justification of speculation is based on the exercise of free initiative: whatever their motivation, each party expects to win on the exchange, and the other party makes it possible. Obviously, if a person buys cheap because he expects its price increase and this occurs, he will gain in the operation, and the seller will relatively lose, but this does not mean that the buyer has behaved unfairly, unless he has engaged in immoral practices such as price rigging, hoarding or spreading false news to cause shortages: the morality of the operation will depend, above all, on having observed the rules of justice in exchange. Thus, speculation contributes to the social function of the market: it provides liquidity (it facilitates the parties to buy or sell whenever they want without excessive cost) and information to the market, and this improves efficiency.

p.352

Speculation is sometimes criticized by the sheer amount of profit that the speculator may earn, quickly and effortlessly (but with risk), but a moral assessment of these actions is not determined simply by the amount of profits, so long as they have been obtained by fair means (on the morals of profits see the divergent views of Arnold 1987 and Brown 1992). Another aspect is risk: speculators take on a risk, but this is not necessarily immoral, as we said before; the fact that some speculators are ruined has more to do with their misjudgment of the circumstances than with the market’s morality.

Electronic and high frequency trading

New information technologies expand and accelerate the possibilities of analysis, decision-making and communication; consequently, finance is becoming more interconnected, faster and more complex—and less human. This may be an advantage in terms of the addition of speed, memory, or power coupled with the subtraction of emotion, distraction, and error. But this does not lessen the moral responsibility of the people who use these technologies.

In the recent decades the growth of electronic trading has provided easy access to the markets without the intervention of intermediaries; this increased competition and developed continuous, integrated and more efficient markets. Afterwards, supercomputers were introduced that operate at superspeed using complex algorithmic programs, and it is here that new moral problems arise.10

A particularly significant form of the use of this technology is high frequency trading (sometimes referred to as “HFT”). These are sophisticated programs that carry out operations in a fraction of second and do it thousands of times a day by holding numerous positions open for very short periods of time. By locating the intermediaries’ computers very close to the markets’ computers, they receive orders a few milliseconds before slow traders; if, for example, a buying order arrives, they can place another order before the selling order arrives from a slower trader, obtaining a minimal profit per unit but multiplied by a very large number of operations. In addition, they anticipate market movements, placing many orders that forestall the actions of slow traders, running ahead of them to get a profit.

High frequency trading is a rent-capturing procedure at the expense of slower traders, and its social benefits are extremely debatable (Angel and McCabe 2013; Cooper et al. 2016; Liu 2014; and Madonna 2013). They provide arbitrage opportunities, identifying small price differences, but the millisecond lead does not provide any significant benefit in liquidity terms; neither does the reduction in transaction costs, due to the narrower spread between bids and ask prices. Furthermore, stuffing the market with fictitious orders can be a type of deception: for example, a trader can launch a large number of fictitious purchase orders to create the false impression that he is trying to make that purchase and cause sales orders from other traders, although the released orders will be canceled immediately. And these practices heighten operations’ endogeneity, giving markets a life of their own, disconnected from the agents’ financial needs,11 and may have destabilizing effects, triggering a chain reaction processed by computers, without human intervention—but with human responsibility—in response to an erratic market movement.

Computers and networks perform vital functions in financial markets: they provide access to more and faster information, they reduce costs and give empowerment to customers. But they can also have negative effects: speed may accentuate volatility, increase risk, hamper some agents’ free access to the market and unfairly discriminate among operators. The technical advantages of computers are undeniable but, from the ethical viewpoint, it is the person’s agency, initiative and freedom that may be at stake, because it is the person who designs the programs and endorses its use who is ultimately responsible for the decisions made by computers.

p.353

Alternative finance

Ethical banking, ethical funds, socially responsible investment, crowdfunding, microfinance

Over the course of history, many investors have felt responsible for the use of their money and did not wish to become collaborators with or accomplices to possible immoral dealings of the companies they financed; or, taking a positive approach, they wished their wealth to be used in economically and socially beneficial activities. From the other side of the market, the investors’ demands have been mirrored with the provision of ethically and socially responsible investment products and in the actions of organizations that try to manage themselves in accordance with ethical standards.

Investors with these concerns often see the financial world as something complex and opaque, in which questionable ethical practices abound. To correct this, new models of financial institutions and products have emerged, such as ethical or sustainable banking, ethical funds, socially responsible investment, impact investing and many others. Their goal is to direct resources towards broader goals than profit, offering savers the possibility of cooperating for the good of the activities they invest in, without sacrificing financial return. The adjectives ethical, sustainable, or responsible differentiate these institutions, but this does not mean that other organizations are not ethical, sustainable or responsible, or that the organizations that do have these adjectives live up to them in everything they do.12

Initially, attention was focused on negative investment criteria, excluding business involved in the production of weapons, tobacco, or pornography, or industries that pollute. Later on, positive criteria were added, so that investment would be made preferentially in socially desirable activities, such as community development, fair trade or renewable energies. And, more recently, shareholder activism was included to get companies to apply environmental, social and governance (ESG) criteria in their actions.

There have been many highly varied innovations in the field of alternative finance. For example, crowdfunding, person-to-person lending and social lending consist of raising funds in a flexible way through the social media, often by means of a large number of small contributions, in order to finance economic, social or hybrid projects. Their ethical appeal arises from their possible social goals and the involvement of communities interested in the project, although they are sometimes criticized for the high interest rates charged to borrowers, uncertainty on guarantees, lack of transparency about the projects and ex-post accountability, and the possible use for illicit activities (as in instances of crowd-funding: Hossain and Oparaocha 2017).

Originally, microcredit consisted of granting small loans to entrepreneurs with the collective guarantee or social control of a group of small entrepreneurs; the commitment to return the funds provided was taken very seriously, and the interest rate was usually high, as justified by the operation’s risk and the interest charged by alternative sources. Microfinance includes microcredits and other instruments (savings, payment systems, insurance) to which their recipients do not have access for geographical reasons or lack of income or collateral. The ultimate goal of microfinance was to combat poverty and foster development by financing sustainable micro-enterprises.

p.354

Microfinance has been highly praised (Grameen Bank, one of the pioneer institutions, and its founder, Muhammad Yunus, were awarded the Nobel Peace Prize in 1976) but it also received criticism, not so much for its goals as for its procedures and results (Argandoña 2010; Schmidt 2012). As a tool for development, it was expected that microfinance institutions were able to cover their costs and make a profit that would attract new investors, ensuring their economic sustainability. But the expectation of a profit and the pressure of investors changed the nature of the lending operations from the creation of microenterprises to more general consumer credit, in competition with commercial banks; interest rates increased and pressures to repay the debt became more aggressive. Behind those developments were changes in the ownership of the institutions, which often ceased to be social enterprises, foundations, or NGOs in order to become for-profit banks.

The expected social results of microcredit have not always been achieved, perhaps because expectations were too high, or because a region’s development depends on more than the existence of small projects targeting a local market that can end up becoming saturated. Microcredit can be used to stabilize a middle class of small entrepreneurs and create jobs, but the debt burden on the poorest limits their ability to eliminate poverty. The future of microfinance is yet to be determined, but now we know more about its possibilities and limitations.13

Islamic finance

Islamic finance is a radical alternative to Western finance, based on the principles of Sharia or Islamic law. It is not intended as a mere correction of the capitalist model as it is based on religious principles: Sharia seeks to develop a way of life, a collective morality and a spirituality. Any human activity, including economic operations, must seek human good and apply principles of justice, equality, harmony and moderation to achieve balance between material and spiritual needs. Islamic finance includes both moral principles and legal regulations that are applied to any activity and, in particular, to the financial institutions created and managed in accordance with Sharia (on the ethical implications of Islamic finance, see Hassan and Kayed 2009; Rice 1999; and Wilson 1997).

Sharia prohibits any financial activity related to the production of or trade in non-permitted goods, such as pigs, alcohol and gambling. Money does not beget money; consequently, it is forbidden to charge interest (riba) on a loan. Costs, profits, and risks must be shared between the parties to the contract: the concept of justice does not refer only to the procedure but also to the results and, above all, it must create value for society. Islamic banks do not just lend money to their customers; they also establish close relationships with them, including a partnership in the business, dispensing advice and providing supervision. Financial institutions are at the service of the community and not only of individuals, and responsible finance includes controlling the behavior of lenders and borrowers, avoiding, for example, over-indebtedness.

Concluding remarks

In the preceding pages we have explained the nature of several ethical issues arising in finance. Such issues are not morally different from other human decisions, because there are no autonomous moral principles for different activities. Nonetheless, each financial asset or endeavor has its own character, whether because of the nature of the transaction, the product itself, the sponsoring institutions, or the circumstances of the overall market. And through it all reside human relationships.

Good financial professionals act for the benefit of their clients. In so doing, these professionals must ask themselves questions such as these: Is it wise for a householder without a regular job to commit a significant portion of his income on a mortgage to buy a home? Do investors have any specific responsibility for the activities of the company in which they place their money? Does the expectation of a great profit justify highly leveraged option trades? Is it lawful to sell a complex financial asset to a client without financial education or experience? The answers to these queries have an economic dimension in terms of variables such as income and expenses, yields and risks, solvency and liquidity. But they also have a moral dimension—the fair, the prudent, and the responsible—which looks toward the flourishing of individuals and the common good of society. This ethical dimension has become more complex in recent decades but it cannot be compromised for some economic variable or reduced to some technical decision of risk and return.

p.355

Finance needs ethics not just to soothe investors’ consciences but to improve the industry’s practices, to develop solid legal and regulatory (not to mention theoretical) frameworks, to sustain appropriate institutional and cultural foundations, and to create the atmosphere of trust without which finance cannot succeed. Good ethics is good finance: not necessarily because it contributes to greater returns, but, above all, because it is a condition for the good management of financial institutions and for the full life of all individuals.

Essential readings

Financial ethics is a very broad field. The reader can find excellent analysis of the most relevant issues in John R. Boatright, Ethics in Finance (2014) and John Hendry, Ethics in Finance: An Introduction (2013). Several edited collections offer incisive accounts and analyses, including A. Argandoña (ed.), The Ethical Dimension of Financial Institutions and Markets (1995a), Boatright (ed.), Financial Ethics: Critical Issues in Theory and Practice (2010) and Andreas R. Prindl and Bimal Prodhan (eds), Ethical Conflicts in Finance (1994), among others. With a focus on financial intermediaries, see Christopher J. Cowton and Paul Thompson, Ethical Banking: Progress and Prospects (1999) and Peter Koslowski, The Ethics of Banking: Conclusions from the Financial Crisis (2011).

For further reading in this volume on the institutions that frame the financial system, see Chapter 18, Property and business and Chapter 21, Regulation, rent seeking, and business ethics. On the causes of the 2008 financial crisis, see Chapter 23, The economic crisis: causes and considerations. On the relation of religious belief (including Islam) to money lending and markets, see Chapter 9, Business ethics and religious belief. On issues related to risk and accountability, see Chapter 31, The accounting profession, the public interest, and human rights.

Notes

  1    There are many studies of the ethical side of the recent crisis: for example, Argandoña (2016), Donaldson (2012), Graafland and van de Ven (2011), Kolb (2010), Nielsen (2010). See also Chapter 23 in this volume.

  2    On the history, status, and function of money, see Guido Hülsmann (2008).

  3    Divergent perspectives on fractional reserve banking may be found in Murray N. Rothbard (2008) and Lawrence White (1989).

  4    In each case, what this information will be depends on factors such as the customer’s ability to understand the transaction and its potential outcomes.

  5    On the ethical problems of insider trading, cf. Engelen and van Liedekerke (2010), McGee (2008).

  6    Bonvin and Dembinski (2002) and Dembinski et al. (2003) discuss the ethical responsibilities of investors.

  7    On the ethics of funds, cf. Hess (2010), Johnsen (2010). Particular ethical issues are discussed by Almeder and Snoeyenbos (1987) on churning; Boatright (1999), Carson (1994) and Palazzo and Rethel (2008) on conflicts of interest.

  8    Overdahl (2010) and Raines and Leathers (1994) deal with the ethical issues of derivatives; Cvjetanovic (2014) and Murdock (2013) address specific derivatives in the recent crisis. On the ethical aspects of securitization, cf. Buchanan (2015), Nielsen (2010) and Schwarcz (2009). The ethical failures of rating agencies in the valuation of derivatives are explained in Scalet and Kelly (2012) and Strier (2008).

p.356

  9    Angel and McCabe (2010) and Koslowski (1995) discuss the ethics of speculation. A particular case is that of short selling (selling securities or other financial instruments that are not currently owned, and subsequently repurchasing them) (Angel and McCabe 2009). This practice adds another ethical issue: the possibility that the short sale will trigger an overreaction in the market, accentuating the fall of the price of the security.

10    Hurlburt et al. (2009), Kraemer et al. (2010) and West (2014) analyze the ethical issues arising from the use of new information and communication technologies in the financial markets.

11    Dark pools are electronic trading networks that facilitate anonymous trading, hiding it from the market to prevent their strategy from becoming known; they are, somehow, defense mechanisms against high frequency operators (Koehn and Koehn 2014).

12    The ethics of socially responsible investing is treated, among others, by Louche and Lydenberg (2010), Mackenzie and Lewis (1999), Sandbu (2012), Sparkes (2002) and Vandekerchkove et al. (2011). For critical perspectives on this form of investing, see Entine (2005).

13    Microfinance is related to bankarization and financial inclusion, which seeks to enable all citizens to access a variety of financial products as a means to overcome significant obstacles to their opportunities, security and participation.

References

Almeder, R.F. and M. Snoeyenbos (1987). “Churning: Ethical and Legal Issues,” Business & Professional Ethics Journal 6:1, 22–31.

Angel, J.J. and D. McCabe (2009). “The Business Ethics of Short Selling and Naked Short Selling,” Journal of Business Ethics 85:1, 239–249.

Angel, J.J. and D. McCabe (2010). “The Ethics of Speculation,” Journal of Business Ethics 90:3, 277–286.

Angel, J.J. and D. McCabe (2013). “Fairness in Financial Markets: The Case of High Frequency Trading,” Journal of Business Ethics 112:4, 585–595.

Angel, J.J. and D. McCabe (2014). “The Ethics of Payments: Paper, Plastic, or Bitcoin,” Journal of Business Ethics 132:3, 603–611.

Argandoña, A. (ed.) (1995a). The Ethical Dimension of Financial Institutions and Markets. Berlin: Springer.

Argandoña, A. (1995b). “The Treatment of Ethical Problems in Financial Institutions and Markets,” in A. Argandoña (ed.), The Ethical Dimension of Financial Institutions and Markets. Berlin: Springer, 1–26.

Argandoña, A. (2010). “Microfinance,” in J.R. Boatright (ed.), Financial Ethics: Critical Issues in Theory and Practice. Hoboken, NJ: John Wiley and Sons, 419–434.

Argandoña, A. (2016). “Three Ethical Dimensions of the Financial Crisis,” in A.G. Malliaris, L. Shaw and H. Shefrin (eds), The Global Financial Crisis: Neglected Ideas from Economics, Psychology, and Values. New York, NY: Oxford University Press, 2016 413-428.

Arnold, N.S. (1987). “Why Profits Are Deserved,” Ethics 97:2, 387–402.

Boatright, J.R. (1999). “Financial Services,” in M. Davis and A. Stark (eds), Conflict of Interest in the Professions. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.

Boatright, J.R. (ed.) (2010). Financial Ethics: Critical Issues in Theory and Practice. Hoboken, NJ: John Wiley and Sons.

Boatright, J.R. (2012). “The Ethics of Risk Management: A Post-Crisis Perspective,” in BBVA Foundation, Values and Ethics for the 21st Century. Madrid: BBVA Foundation, 473–496.

Boatright, J.R. (2014). Ethics in Finance. Oxford: Wiley Blackwell.

Bonvin, J-M. and P.H. Dembinski (2002). “Ethical Issues in Financial Activities,” Journal of Business Ethics 37:2, 187–192.

Brown, G.A. (1992). “Are Profits Deserved?” Journal of Business Ethics 11:2, 105–114.

Buchanan, B.G. (2015). “Securitization: A Financing Vehicle for All Seasons?” Journal of Business Ethics DOI 10.1007/s10551-015-2636-y.

Carson, T.L. (1994). “Conflicts of Interest,” Journal of Business Ethics 13:5, 387–404.

Cooper, R., M. Davis and B. Van Vliet (2016). “The mysterious ethics of high-frequency trading,” Business Ethics Quarterly 26:1, 1–22.

Cowton, C.J. (2002). “Integrity, Responsibility and Affinity: Three Aspects of Ethics in Banking,” Business Ethics: A European Review 11:4, 393–400.

Cowton, C.J. and P. Thompson (1999). Ethical Banking: Progress and Prospects. London: Financial Times Business.

p.357

Cvjetanovic, M. (2014). “Collateralised Debt Obligations (CDOs): An Update,” Moral Cents, Seven Pillars Institute, 3:1, 29–52.

Davies, H. (2001). “Ethics in Regulation,” Business Ethics: A European Review 10:4, 280–287.

Dembinski, P.H. (2009). Finance: Servant or Deceiver? Financialization at the Crossroads. London: Palgrave Macmillan.

Dembinski, P.H., J.-M. Bonvin, E. Dommen and F.-M. Monnet (2003). “The Ethical Foundations of Responsible Investment,” Journal of Business Ethics 48:2, 203–213.

Donaldson, T. (2010). “Hedge Funds,” in J.R. Boatright (ed.), Financial Ethics: Critical Issues in Theory and Practice. Hoboken, NJ: John Wiley and Sons, 239–252.

Donaldson, T. (2012). “Three Ethical Roots of the Economic Crisis,” Journal of Business Ethics 106:1, 5–8.

Engelen, P-J. and L. van Liedekerke (2010). “Insider Trading,” in J.R. Boatright (ed.), Financial Ethics: Critical Issues in Theory and Practice. Hoboken, NJ: John Wiley and Sons, 199–221.

Entine, J. (ed.) (2005). Pension Fund Politics: The Dangers of Socially Responsible Investing. Washington, DC: AEI Press.

Graafland, J.J. and B.W. Van de Ven (2011). “The Credit Crisis and the Moral Responsibility of Professionals in Finance,” Journal of Business Ethics 103:4, 605–619.

Green, C.F. (1989). “Business Ethics in Banking,” Journal of Business Ethics 8:8, 631–634.

Hassan, M.K. and R.N. Kayed (2009). “The Global Financial Crisis, Risk Management and Social Justice in Islamic Finance,” ISRA International Journal of Islamic Finance 1:1, 33–58.

Hayek, F.A. (1976). The Denationalisation of Money. London: Institute for Economic Affairs.

Heath, E. (2010). “Fairness in Financial Markets,” in J.R. Boatright (ed.) Financial Ethics: Critical Issues in Theory and Practice. Hoboken, NJ: John Wiley and Sons, 163–178.

Hendry, J. (2013). Ethics in Finance. An Introduction. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Hess, D. (2010). “Pension Funds,” in J.R. Boatright (ed.), Financial Ethics: Critical Issues in Theory and Practice. Hoboken, NJ: John Wiley and Sons, 359–372.

Hossain, M. and G. Oparaocha (2017). “Crowdfunding: Motives, Definitions, Typology and Ethical Challenges.” Entrepreneurship Research Journal 7:2. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1515/erj-2015-0045.

Hülsmann, J.G. (2008). The Ethics of Money Production. Auburn, AL: Ludwig von Mises Institute.

Hurlburt, G.F., K.W. Miller and J.M. Voas (2009). “An Ethical Analysis of Automation, Risk, and the Financial Crises of 2008,” IEEE IT Professional 11, 14–19.

Johnsen, D.B. (2010). “Mutual Funds,” in J.R. Boatright (ed.), Financial Ethics: Critical Issues in Theory and Practice. Hoboken, NJ: John Wiley and Sons, 339–358.

Johnson, T.C. (2015). “Reciprocity as a Foundation of Financial Economics,” Journal of Business Ethics 131:1, 43–67.

Kane, E.J. (2014). “Regulation and Supervision: An Ethical Perspective,” in A.N. Berger, P. Molyneux and J.O.S. Wilson (eds), Oxford Handbook of Banking. New York, NY: Oxford University Press, 2nd edition, 505–526.

Kleinau, C. (2014). “Ethics in Finance: Applying Ethical Theory to Guide Decisions and Analysis in Finance.” Available at: http://ssrn.com/abstract=2512668.

Koehn, D. (1994). The Ground of Professional Ethics. London: Routledge.

Koehn, D. (2010). Living with the Dragon: Thinking and Acting Ethically in a World of Unintended Consequences. New York, NY: Routledge.

Koehn, J.L. and D. Koehn (2014). “Ethical Issues with Dark Liquidity and the Ethics of Possible Remedies,” Moral Cents, Seven Pillars Institute 3:2, 3–29.

Kolb, R.W. (ed.) (2010). Lessons from the Financial Crisis: Causes, Consequences, and Our Economic Future. Hoboken, NJ: John Wiley and Sons.

Koslowski, P. (1995). “The Ethics of Banking. On the Ethical Economy of the Credit and Capital Market, of Speculation and Insider Trading in the German Experience,” in A. Argandoña (ed.), The Ethical Dimension of Financial Institutions and Markets. Berlin: Springer, 180–232.

Koslowski, P. (2011). The Ethics of Banking: Conclusions from the Financial Crisis. New York, NY: Springer.

Kraemer, F., K. van Overveld and M. Peterson (2010). “Is There an Ethics of Algorithms?” Ethics and Information Technology 13:3, 251–260.

Lietaer, B. and J. Lunne (2013). Rethinking Money: New Currencies Turn Scarcity into Prosperity. San Francisco, CA: Berrett-Koehler.

Liu, T.C.W. (2014). “The New Financial Industry,” Alabama Law Review 65:3, 567–623.

Louche, C. and S. Lydenberg (2010). “Responsible Investing,” in J.R. Boatright (ed.), Financial Ethics: Critical Issues in Theory and Practice. Hoboken, NJ: John Wiley and Sons, 393–417.

p.358

Mackenzie, C. and A. Lewis (1999). “Morals and Markets: The Case for Ethical Investing,” Business Ethics Quarterly 9:3, 439–452.

Mackenzie, D. (2008). An Engine, Not a Camera. How Financial Models Shape Markets. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

Madonna, L. (2013). “The Ethics of High Frequency Trading,” Moral Cents, Seven Pillars Institute, 2:1, 17–25.

McGee, R.W. (2008). “Applying Ethics to Insider Trading,” Journal of Business Ethics 77:2, 205–217.

Munro, J.H. (2003). “The Medieval Origins of the Financial Revolution: Usury, Rentes, and Negotiability,” The International History Review 25:3, 505–562.

Murdock, C.W. (2013). “Credit Default Swaps: Dubious Instruments.” Harvard Business Law Review Online, 133–141. Available at: http://lawecommons.luc.edu/cgi/viewcontent.cgi?article=1460&context=facpubs.

Nielsen, R.P. (2010). “High-Leverage Finance Capitalism, the Economic Crisis, Structurally Related Ethics Issues, and Potential Reforms,” Business Ethics Quarterly 20:2, 299–330.

Overdahl, J.A. (2010). “Derivative Contracts,” in J.R. Boatright (ed.), Financial Ethics: Critical Issues in Theory and Practice. Hoboken, NJ: John Wiley and Sons, 223–238.

Painter, R. (2010). “The Moral Responsibilities of Investment Bankers,” University of St. Thomas Law Journal 8:1, 5–28.

Palazzo, G. and L. Rethel (2008). “Conflicts of Interest in Financial Intermediation,” Journal of Business Ethics 81:1, 193–207.

Poszar, A., T. Adrian, A. Ashcraft and H. Boesky (2013). “Shadow Banking,” Federal Reserve Bank of New York Policy Review Staff Report No. 458.

Prindl, A.R. and B. Prodhan (eds) (1994). Ethical Conflicts in Finance. Oxford: Blackwell.

Raines, J.P. and C.G. Leathers (1994). “Financial Derivative Instruments and Social Ethics,” Journal of Business Ethics 13:3, 197–204.

Reynolds, J.N. and E. Newell (2011). The Ethics of Investment Banking. Houndmills, UK: Palgrave Macmillan.

Rice, G. (1999). “Islamic Ethics and the Implication for Business,” Journal of Business Ethics 18:4, 345–358.

Rothbard, M.N. (2008). The Mystery of Banking. Auburn, AL: Ludwig von Mises Institute, 2nd edition.

Ryan, L.V., A.K. Buchholtz and R.W. Kolb (2010). “New Directions in Corporate Governance and Finance: Implications for Business Ethics Research,” Business Ethics Quarterly 20:4, 673–694.

Sandbu, M. (2012). “Stakeholder Duties: On the Moral Responsibility of Corporate Investors,” Journal of Business Ethics 109:1, 97–107.

Scalet, S. and T.F. Kelly (2012). “The Ethics of Credit Rating Agencies: What Happened and the Way Forward,” Journal of Business Ethics 111:4, 477–490.

Schmidt, R.H. (2012). “Ethics in Microfinance,” in BBVA Foundation, Values and Ethics for the 21st Century. Madrid: BBVA Foundation, 523–558.

Schwarcz, S. (2009). “The Future of Securitization,” in R.W. Kolb (ed.), Lessons from the Financial Crisis: Causes, Consequences, and Our Economic Future. Hoboken, NJ: John Wiley and Sons, 595–600.

Shefrin, H. and M. Statman (1993). “Ethics, Fairness and Efficiency in Financial Markets,” Financial Analysts Journal 49:6, 21–29.

Shiller, R.J. (2012). Finance and the Good Society. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

Sparkes, R. (2002). Socially Responsible Investment. A Global Revolution. Chichester, UK: John Wiley and Sons.

Strier, F. (2008). “Rating and the Raters: Conflict of Interest in the Credit Rating Firms,” Business and Society Review 113:4, 533–553.

Termes, R. (1995). “Ethics in Financial Institutions,” in A. Argandoña (ed.), The Ethical Dimension of Financial Institutions and Markets. Berlin: Springer, 118–135.

Tollison, R. (2012). “The Economic Theory of Rent Seeking,” Public Choice 152:1, 73–82.

Vandekerchkove, W., J. Leys, K. Alm, B. Sholtens, S. Signori and H. Schäfer (eds) (2011). Responsible Investment in Times of Turmoil. New York, NY: Springer.

West, J. (2014). “Quantitative Method in Finance: From Detachment to Ethical Management,” Journal of Business Ethics 129:3, 599–611.

White L.H. (1989). Competition and Currency: Essays on Free Banking and Money. New York, NY: New York University.

Wilson, R. (1997). “Islamic Finance and Ethical Investment,” International Journal of Social Economics 24:11, 1325–1342.

Young, P.C. (2010). “Risk Management,” in J.R. Boatright (ed.), Financial Ethics: Critical Issues in Theory and Practice. Hoboken, NJ: John Wiley and Sons, 495–508.

..................Content has been hidden....................

You can't read the all page of ebook, please click here login for view all page.
Reset
3.149.247.159