Chapter 6
Vulnerability to Poverty: A Multidimensional Evaluation

6.1 Introduction

Vulnerability is concerned with security risks. We can broadly define it in terms of a system's exposure and capacity to deal adequately with distress. For instance, a situation of economic vulnerability arises when a country faces an economic shock. Similarly, an ecosystem's exposure to climatic shocks may be regarded as a case of environmental vulnerability. A farmer with a low income from agriculture may be nonpoor currently. But since his agricultural output depends on the weather conditions, he may become poor in the future if the weather badly affects production. In the dimension of health, vulnerability may be regarded as a situation where a person with a reasonably good health condition currently will undergo an incident of health problem so that he becomes health-poor over time. (See Dercon and Krishnan, 2000, for an illustration). A person with a contractual nature of employment may be vulnerable to unemployment in the future (see, for example, Basu and Nolen, 2005).

From the aforementioned illustrations, it is clear that the notion of vulnerability is forward-looking. In the study of vulnerability, our concern should be not only with current conditions, such as income and health status, but also with the risks a person faces and his ability to avert, bring down, and conquer these. On the other hand, in the standard poverty analysis, both intertemporal and cross section, the analysis is based on observable information, more precisely, on the assumption of complete certainty. As a result, the analysis of vulnerability requires a separate treatment.

The study of vulnerability is quite important because of its highly significant implications for economic efficiency and long-term individual welfare. Many individuals face adversity in terms of continued illness, natural calamities, and other risks. These people can fall into poverty in the wake of adverse shocks. In consequence, the removal of vulnerability should be a concern of high priority from policy perspective. In the words of Sen (1999, p. 1): “The challenge of development includes not only the elimination of persistent and endemic deprivation, but also the removal of vulnerability to sudden and severe destitution.” Protection of “vulnerable groups during episodes of macroeconomic contraction is vital to poverty reductions in developing countries” (World Bank, 1997, p. 1).

Klasen and Povel (2013) argued that vulnerability at the individual level can be broadly classified into the following four broad categories: (i) vulnerability representing uninsured exposure to risk; (ii) vulnerability as a quantifier of low expected utility; (iii) vulnerability indicating expected poverty; and (iv) vulnerability to poverty. Discussions on the first three categories of vulnerability were made, among others, by Hoddinott and Quisumbing (2003); Ligon and Schechter (2003), and Gaiha and Imai (2009) (see also Hoogeveen et al., 2004). Vulnerability to poverty was introduced and analyzed by Calvo and Dercon (2013). (See Chakravarty et al., 2016; Fujii, 2016, for recent discussions.) In order to discuss these four divisions of vulnerability in greater detail, we assume that income is the only dimension of well-being.

Vulnerability indicating uninsured exposure to risk determines the extent to which income shocks yield changes in consumption (see Townsend, 1994; Amin et al., 2003; Skoufias and Quisumbing, 2005). The concerns of this concept of vulnerability are changes in the current magnitudes of consumption and not current sizes of consumption. This approach ignores a person's temperament about risks.

Vulnerability manifesting low expected utility identifies vulnerability with variability in a positive monotonic way in the sense that an increase in variability is regarded as a higher level of vulnerability. In the theory of statistical decision-making, there has been a long tradition of employing the variance as a measure of risk (Rothschild and Stiglitz, 1970). A sophisticated formulation of this was developed by Ligon and Schechter (2003). To get an insight of the underlying central idea, we consider two individuals, each of whom has the same expected consumption, not below some exogenously given norm, in some future period. It is also true that while for the first person there is a positive probability of destitution in the future, for the second person no such risk exists. It is quite likely that positive probability of adversity in the future period will relegate the first person to a situation of vulnerability. Since vulnerability is a forward-looking concept, it is evident that the two individuals should not be treated identically in terms of vulnerability. According to Ligon and Schechter (2003), vulnerability in a setting of this type can be interpreted as low expected utility.

The Ligon–Schechter index of vulnerability is given by the difference between the utility received from a threshold income, income poverty line, and the individual's expected utility obtained from income in a vulnerable situation. A higher (positive) difference between the two utility values indicates a greater level of vulnerability. This notion of vulnerability regards a person as nonvulnerable if his income is not below the poverty line (see also Glewwe and Hall, 1998; Dercon, 2002; Coudouel and Hentschel, 2000). Since the formulation depends directly on the von Neumann–Morgenstern utility function, an important characteristic of this approach is that it takes into account an individual's attitudes toward risks in an explicit manner. The harshness and possibility of disturbance on individual welfare are incorporated directly into the framework because of nonconstancy of the utility function and probabilistic formulation. Since all the individuals are assumed to possess the same utility function, levels of vulnerability are comparable across persons. Elbers and Gunning (2003) extended the Ligon–Schechter framework over an infinite time horizon. In Morduch (1994), vulnerability was expressed in terms of deviations from the permanent income poverty line.

Vulnerability as expected poverty deals with the risk of an individual's income falling below the income poverty line. This notion of vulnerability was introduced by Ravallion (1988) and advanced and discussed further by Holzmann and Jorgensen (1999). An analysis of this approach was developed in a more formalistic manner by Chaudhuri et al. (2002), which expresses the probability that an individual's income will fall below an exogenous income poverty line. (See also Christiaensen and Boisvert, 2000; Chaudhuri, 2003). However, it does not incorporate the awareness about risks. An individual's status in terms of vulnerability relies simply on some expected income. Hoddinott and Quisumbing (2003) made an attempt to address this shortcoming by considering vulnerability as expected poverty using the Foster et al. (1984) poverty index. When the negative of poverty is interpreted as utility, the Arrow (1965)–Pratt (1964) absolute risk aversion measure, an index of the extent to which a person is risk-averse, for the underlying utility function, increases as the value of the associated parameter increases. However, empirical findings did not support such a risk preference unambiguously (see Hoddinott and Quisumbing, 2003 and Binswanger, 1981). Additional empirical applications of this approach can be found in Suryahadi and Sumarto (2003); Kamanou and Morduch (2004); Christiaensen and Subbarao (2005), and Günther and Harttgen (2009). In Pritchett et al. (2000), vulnerability has been defined in terms of the probability of tumbling into poverty in three consecutive periods.

The concept of vulnerability to poverty was initiated by Calvo and Dercon (2013). They established an axiomatic characterization of an index of vulnerability as a weighted average of future state-contingent deprivations, where the weights are the probabilities of state-contingent returns in the future. “Ligon and Schechter's measure is the expected poverty gap, whereas Calvo and Dercon's measure is the expected Chakravarty index and Kamanou and Morduch (2004) employs the expected Foster–Greer–Thorbecke (FGT) index” (Dutta et al., 2011, p. 645). More generally, these indices are essentially expected poverty indices. In a different contribution, Calvo and Dercon (2009) showed how their index, “which in itself was based on the Chakravarty measure of poverty” (op.cit., p. 46), can be amended as a dynamic and forward-looking index of vulnerability. Dutta et al. (2011) developed an axiomatic characterization of an index of vulnerability that relies explicitly on the current and future incomes. Therefore, while in the Calvo–Dercon approach, deprivations depend on future incomes, the Dutta–Foster–Mishra framework allows us to look at relative changes under vulnerability.

In a recent contribution, López-Calva and Ortiz-Juarez (2014) suggested a view of the middle class that relies on vulnerability to poverty. They employed panel data for income to determine the level of comparable income corresponding to a low probability of falling into poverty. This in turn defines the lower bound of the middle class income. The countries they have considered in their analysis are Chile, Mexico, and Peru.

The examples provided at the beginning of this section clearly show that, similar to poverty, vulnerability is a multidimensional phenomenon (see Calvo, 2008). The objective of this chapter is to study vulnerability to poverty from a multidimensional perspective. This notion of vulnerability represents the strains laid down by the threat of multidimensional poverty. As a background material, we present a brief review of one-dimensional measurement of vulnerability to poverty in the next section. Section 6.3 deals with an axiomatic analysis of multidimensional vulnerability to poverty. Finally, Section 6.4 winds up the chapter. A brief analysis of the Calvo and Dercon (2009) amended index is also presented in this section.

6.2 A Review of One-Dimensional Measurement

Since the one-dimensional approach to vulnerability to poverty measurement is closely related to the multidimensional analysis of the issue, we begin this section with a rigorous discussion on the former. For expositional ease, we assume that income is the only dimension of human well-being. In addition, initially the analysis is carried out at the individual level.

The indices of vulnerability we scrutinize here are based on anticipated changes, that is, they are ex-ante measures in the sense that they incorporate future uncertainty with reference to income. Thus, income is regarded as an uncertain prospect. An absolutely necessary characteristic of these indices is that the underlying risks are downside risks, that is, in the future, there is possibility of downward trend of income. Individual vulnerability here is developed in terms of shortfall of income from the exogenously given income poverty line resulting from economic and other shocks.

Since income is considered as an uncertain prospect, there are different levels of returns on the prospect. These returns are state-contingent or state-dependent outcomes. A state of nature is a situation for the prospect that can arise in the future. Accordingly, by a state-contingent return we mean a return whenever a particular state materializes. In order to illustrate this, consider a farmer for whom there is a high impact of weather conditions (rainfall) on crop production. Relevant states of nature are the rainfall conditions, say: (i) drought, (ii) less than barely sufficient but not drought, (iii) barely sufficient, (iv) optimum, and (v) more than optimum (flood). There is a return associated with each state. These are state-contingent returns.

Assume that the society under consideration consists of n individuals and k states, where c06-math-001 is arbitrary and c06-math-002 is an integer. We denote the set of states by c06-math-003. In order to compare individual vulnerabilities across persons, we will assume throughout the section that the set of states remain the same for all individuals in the society. For individual i, the associated state-contingent returns are represented by a vector c06-math-004, that is, c06-math-005 is the unique income that individual i receives if state j emerges; c06-math-006, c06-math-007. As a consequence, when production of a crop gets affected by variations in rainfall, different levels of rainfall describe the states, and the level of production, when a particular state comes into perceptible existence, is the state-contingent return.

Individual i assumes that the probability of appearance of state j is c06-math-008. We denote the vector of probabilities c06-math-009 by c06-math-010. Evidently, c06-math-011 for all c06-math-012, c06-math-013 and c06-math-014, c06-math-015. Since the return c06-math-016 is uniquely associated with state j, we can as well say that c06-math-017 comes into existence with probability c06-math-018. For any given state j, these probabilities are likely to vary across persons. That is, for any two persons i and h, and for any state j, c06-math-019 need not be the same as c06-math-020, where c06-math-021 and c06-math-022. To illustrate this, we consider two farmers, one of whom has easy access to deep tube well for pumping out underground water if the rainfall is inadequate for crop production. However, for the other person, such a facility does not exist. Therefore, if the rainfall for crop production is not at the requisite level, while it is highly unlikely that the former person's crop production will be badly affected by drought, for the latter individual, this chance is quite high. In other words, the probability of appearance of “drought” is quite low for the first person, whereas for the second person, the probability is quite high. In general, such differences arise because the probabilities may be affected by some external factors, which cannot be ignored. Hence, these probabilities are subjective probabilities – they are based on personal feelings.

Denote the exogenously given threshold limit, the income poverty line, by c06-math-023, and assume, as in Chapter 3, that c06-math-024, where c06-math-025, that is, z takes on values in a finite nondegenerate positive interval of c06-math-026, the nonnegative part of the real line c06-math-027. We say that individual i is poor in state j, equivalently, state j is meager for i, if c06-math-028. Otherwise, that is, if c06-math-029, the person is nonpoor in the state, equivalently, the state is nonmeager for him. Person i is identified as vulnerable if there is at least one state j such that c06-math-030 and c06-math-031. This can be regarded as the vulnerable analog to the contention of identification of a poor person arising in an income poverty situation. A one-dimensional vulnerable situation involving the state-contingent returns c06-math-032, the corresponding probability vector c06-math-033 and the poverty line c06-math-034 may be expressed more compactly as c06-math-035, say, where c06-math-036 is the nonnegative orthant of the k-dimensional Euclidean space c06-math-037, and c06-math-038 is nonnegative k-dimensional unit simplex, the set of all k-coordinated vectors whose coordinates are nonnegative real numbers that add up to 1. Let c06-math-039 denote the set of all one-dimensional vulnerable situations for person i, that is, c06-math-040 . The censored state-contingent return vector associated with c06-math-041 is denoted by c06-math-042, where c06-math-043.

Since we focus on the downside risk, that is, given that each c06-math-044 has a chance of being less than z, the possibility of future poverty occurrence is considered in the framework. In order to determine vulnerability at the individual level, it may be worthwhile to consider the shortfalls of the state-contingent returns from the poverty line in different states of nature. For any person i, these shortfalls, when expressed in relative or proportionate terms, are given by c06-math-045. By definition, each of them is homogeneous of degree 0, that is, invariant under equiproportionate changes in the corresponding state-contingent return and the threshold limit. We refer to them as vulnerability deprivation indicators, which, for a given threshold limit, are decreasing in state-level returns. They are positive if and only if state-dependent returns are below the threshold limit. The issue of considering a vulnerable person's deprivations parallels the idea of looking into the poverty shortfall of an income-poor person.

For any person i, the situations of the type c06-math-046 are transformed into vulnerability levels experienced by person i using a function c06-math-047. In more explicit terms, c06-math-048. The function c06-math-049 can be designated as the individual vulnerability index. The presence of superscript i in c06-math-050 explicitly recognizes that c06-math-051 determines the extent of poverty suffered by person i under probable realization of different states. For any c06-math-052, c06-math-053 determines the extent of vulnerability that the person undergoes.

We now suggest the following axioms for the individual vulnerability index. Variants of some of these axioms were discussed by Calvo and Dercon (2013), Chakravarty and Chattopadhyay (2015), and Chakravarty et al. (2015).

  1. State-Restricted Focus: For any c06-math-054, if for some c06-math-055, c06-math-056, then c06-math-057, where c06-math-058.
  2. State-Restricted Monotonicity: For any c06-math-059, if for some c06-math-060, c06-math-061, c06-math-062, then c06-math-063, where c06-math-064.
  3. Across-States Transfer: For any c06-math-065 if for some c06-math-066, then c06-math-067, where c06-math-068 for all c06-math-069 and c06-math-070.
  4. State-Restricted Monotonicity in Threshold Limit: For any c06-math-071, if for at least one state c06-math-072, c06-math-073 and c06-math-074, then c06-math-075, where c06-math-076 and c06-math-077.
  5. Severity of Downside Risks: For any c06-math-078, if for some c06-math-079, c06-math-080, then c06-math-081, where c06-math-082, c06-math-083, c06-math-084 and c06-math-085.
  6. State-Restricted Boundedness: The index c06-math-086 is bounded between 0 and 1, where the lower bound is achieved if for any c06-math-087, c06-math-088 is such that c06-math-089 for all c06-math-090. c06-math-091 reaches its upper bound if for any c06-math-092, c06-math-093 for all c06-math-094 .
  7. State-Restricted Replication Principle: For any c06-math-095, suppose that for each c06-math-096, the state-contingent return c06-math-097 is replicated m times and the corresponding probability value c06-math-098 is split equally among the replicated figures of c06-math-099, then c06-math-100, where c06-math-101 is the mk-coordinated vector of replicated returns and c06-math-102 is the mk-coordinated vector of split probabilities, c06-math-103 being any integer.
  8. Continuity in State-Contingent Returns: For given c06-math-104, c06-math-105 varies continuously with respect to variations in returns such that the vulnerability status of the person remains unchanged.

One common feature of these state-restricted properties is that they can be termed as individualistic axioms in the sense that the underlying operations involve only one person's vulnerability. The focus axiom here demands that an increase in the return from a nondeprived state does not change the vulnerability index. Since vulnerability is concerned with downside risk, this axiom is quite plausible. If the low return from a state with a positive probability of being deprived reduces further, then the extent of vulnerability increases. The current version of the monotonicity axiom makes this sensible claim. To illustrate this axiom, suppose that person i foresees that because of economic shocks, his current income 620 may reduce to 610, 590, and 580, respectively, with probabilities c06-math-106, and c06-math-107. Assume that the threshold income c06-math-108. Then c06-math-109 and c06-math-110. Suppose that the person revises his prediction under some apprehension that the lowest anticipated income 580 will actually be 570. Now, given that the probabilities and the other anticipated incomes remain unchanged, we have c06-math-111 and the monotonicity axiom demands that c06-math-112.

According to the present form of the transfer axiom, vulnerability goes up under a transfer of return from a state with low positive return and high downside risk to another state possessing a higher return but not higher risk. The intuitive reasoning behind this postulate is that downside risk is not lower in state q than in state j, and the transfer decreases the lower return in q further and increases that in j, which already had higher return. Hence, vulnerability should increase. Undoubtedly, such a transfer may be regarded as an across-states regressive transfer. Suppose in the aforementioned example, c06-math-113 is generated from c06-math-114 by a regressive transfer of income from state 3 to state 2. Since state 3 has a lower return but higher probability than state 2, according to the across-states transfer axiom, c06-math-115. We note the similarity and dissimilarity between the income poverty transfer axiom and the transfer axiom proposed here. While for a notion of transfer to be valid in the income poverty case, there should be at least two persons; here we need existence of at least two states for the prospect, and it concerns only one person.

If in a deprived state, which has a positive probability of appearance, the person becomes more deprived resulting from an increase in the threshold limit, then vulnerability should increase unambiguously. The variant of the axiom of monotonicity in poverty line suggested in the current section asserts this. Since vulnerability is concerned with downside risk, if this type of risk of return from a state with low return goes up and the corresponding risk from a state with high return goes down, then evidently vulnerability should demonstrate an upward trend. This legitimate requirement is affirmed by the axiom of severity of downside risk. This postulate is a unique characteristic of the vulnerability index and does not parallel any standard poverty property. Given that c06-math-116 and c06-math-117, suppose that person i increases his subjective probability of falling his current income from 620 to 580 by c06-math-118 and reduces that of falling to c06-math-119 by c06-math-120. Hence, c06-math-121 changes to c06-math-122. Of states 2 and 3, originally the latter had a lower return accompanied by a higher probability. Hence, the conditions laid down in the severity of downside risk axiom are satisfied. As a result, c06-math-123.

The boundedness axiom related to the one-dimensional vulnerability of a person insists that vulnerability index takes on a finite value lying between 0 and 1, where the minimum value 0 is attained if none of the returns falls below the threshold limit so that the person has a nonvulnerable status. It obtains its upper bound 1 if the return from each state is 0 so that the person is maximally deprived. Since there is no possibility of further reduction of the return from any state, this maximum value is achieved irrespective of the probability distribution. To understand the state-restricted replication principle, let c06-math-124 and c06-math-125. Assume that each state-contingent return is replicated twice. Then c06-math-126 and c06-math-127. The individual vulnerability levels of the two situations are the same. The final axiom, continuity in state-specific returns ensures smooth behavior of the vulnerability index with respect to variations in returns under ceteris paribus conditions. Note that change in one probability will require a change in at least one different probability, so the sum of all probabilities equals 1.

As an illustrative example, we consider the Calvo and Dercon (2013) individual vulnerability index defined as

where the constant c06-math-129 controls risk awareness. As Dutta et al. (2011) noted, this is the expected Chakravarty (1983) poverty index. The restriction c06-math-130 ensures that the focused, normalized, and continuous index c06-math-131 satisfies the monotonicity (in returns), transfer, and downside risk severity axioms. It increases if the poverty threshold increases under the minor restriction considered. For c06-math-132, it is the proportionate gap between the poverty line and the expected state-dependent return. This is the situation of risk neutrality. On the other hand, as c06-math-133, c06-math-134. This index is a member of a family of expected poverty or deprivation indices given by c06-math-135, where c06-math-136 satisfying c06-math-137 is a transformed deprivation indicator. It is also assumed to be decreasing, continuous, and strictly convex in state-contingent return. Decreasingness and strict convexity ensure satisfaction of the monotonicity and the transfer axioms, respectively. The normalization condition c06-math-138 guarantees attainability of the lower bound of c06-math-139. Depending on the forms of c06-math-140 chosen, we have different vulnerability indicators. In the Calvo–Dercon case, c06-math-141.

If the transformed deprivation indicator is given by c06-math-142, where c06-math-143 is a parameter, then the expected poverty index c06-math-144 turns out to be the expected Foster et al. (1984) poverty index (see Kamanou and Morduch, 2002):

6.2 equation

Under the parametric restriction c06-math-146, all the vulnerability axioms are abided by c06-math-147. For c06-math-148, c06-math-149 coincides with c06-math-150 if c06-math-151. For a given c06-math-152, as the value of c06-math-153 increases, more weight is assigned to higher proportionate gaps. In addition, given c06-math-154, an increase in the value of c06-math-155 does not increase the value of the index.

Assuming that all the state-contingent returns are positive, we may use c06-math-156 as a transformed deprivation indicator. The resulting vulnerability index becomes the expected Watts (1968) individual poverty function, defined as

Because of positivity restriction of the state-contingent returns, c06-math-158 is not bounded above. However, it meets all other axioms.

As the final illustrative example, we consider the Bourguignon and Chakravarty (2003) individual vulnerability index defined as

6.4 equation

where c06-math-160 and c06-math-161 are parameters. This index agrees with all the vulnerability postulates we have analyzed. It, however, does not fit in the structure c06-math-162 unless c06-math-163, in which case it coincides with c06-math-164.

We define the one-dimensional global or overall vulnerability index c06-math-165 as a nonnegative real-valued function of all one-dimensional vulnerable situations of different persons. As we have assumed, the set of states is the same for all persons, and the threshold income is exogenous. For a set of population c06-math-166 consisting of n individuals, where c06-math-167 is arbitrary , let c06-math-168 denote the set of all one-dimensional vulnerable situations, when all the individuals are taken together, that is, c06-math-169. Let c06-math-170, or, c06-math-171 (for short) stand for any arbitrarily chosen c06-math-172. By definition, c06-math-173. The set c06-math-174 is the domain of our global vulnerability index c06-math-175. Formally, c06-math-176.

As an illustrative example, we regard c06-math-177 as the arithmetic average of individual vulnerability indices (see also Calvo and Dercon, 2013). Then our global vulnerability index c06-math-178 is defined as

where c06-math-180 is arbitrary. The idea of defining the aggregate vulnerability index as a function of individual indices may be regarded as representing a property, which we can refer to as independence of irrelevant information. This is because all individualistic nonvulnerability features are ignored in this definition.

By construction, the vulnerability index c06-math-181 in (6.5) obeys subgroup decomposability. Thus, it has nice policy relevance in the sense that it becomes helpful in identifying higher vulnerability affected subgroups that may become a policy adviser's targeted subgroups for reducing social vulnerability.

It possesses several interesting properties, assuming that c06-math-182 unambiguously meets all the axioms proposed earlier.

  1. i. It is bounded between 0 and 1, where the lower bound is achieved if everybody in the society has a nonvulnerable status. The upper bound is attained if all the individuals are subject to maximum deprivation in all states. (For the index associated with (6.3), the upper bound is not attained.)
  2. ii. It varies continuously for changes in meager achievement levels, under certain ceteris paribus conditions.
  3. iii. It meets a strong monotonicity property in the sense that an increase in an individual's income vulnerability increases its value. This property parallels the strong Pareto principle analyzed in Chapter 1.
  4. iv. Discussion on the next postulate relies on the following definition.

In state q, person i has higher deprivation than person h in state j, and the corresponding probability for i's deprivation is not lower than that for h's. The regressive transfer (of size c06-math-200) takes place from person i's return in state q to the return for person h in state j. Since the probability vectors in the two situations and the threshold limit remain the same, the regressive transfer should increase global vulnerability. Further, given that the regressive transfer occurs between two persons, we can refer to it as a one-dimensional nonindividualistic transfer. In addition, it involves two states. We can present the following axiom for our one-dimensional overall vulnerability index c06-math-201.

  1. Across-States One-Dimensional Nonindividualistic Regressive Transfer: If the one-dimensional global vulnerable situation c06-math-202 is obtained from the situation c06-math-203 by a nonindividualistic regressive transfer, c06-math-204.
  1. i. Any reordering of individual vulnerability levels does not change the value of c06-math-205. Hence, the individuals are separated only by vulnerability levels.
  2. ii. Any m-fold replication of the population leaves global vulnerability unchanged, where c06-math-206 is an integer. In consequence, this characteristic enables us to compare vulnerabilities of two societies with different population sizes. This population replication principle is stated under the supposition that the vectors of state-contingent returns and probabilities remain unchanged.

Although properties stated in (i)–(vi) are examined for the global index c06-math-207 that meets subgroup decomposability, they may as well be regarded as desirable postulates for a general global vulnerability index c06-math-208, which may not be subgroup decomposable. One such possible example is c06-math-209, where c06-math-210.

We conclude this section by providing one illustration of c06-math-211 using c06-math-212 as the individual index. The resulting global index turns out to be

6.6 equation

where, as before, c06-math-214 and c06-math-215 are parameters. The major difference between this index and the overall Foster–Greer–Thorbecke index, which arises when c06-math-216, and the Calvo–Dercon expected Chakravarty index c06-math-217 is that, while in the former the individual expected income poverty levels are aggregated nonlinearly across persons, the latter two employ a simple linear aggregation.

6.3 Multidimensional Representation of Vulnerability to Poverty: An Axiomatic Investigation

As we have argued in several chapters earlier, the well-being of a population is a multidimensional issue. Hence, to get a complete picture of individual and social vulnerabilities in a population, it is necessary to investigate the problem from a multidimensional perspective. Since in the capability-functioning approach, capability failure captures the notion of deprivation that people experience in day-to-day living conditions, it is a multidimensional phenomenon. Consequently, multidimensional vulnerability to poverty is a problem of expected capability deprivation.

As in Chapter 3, we denote the number of dimensions of well-being in a society consisting of n individuals by d, where c06-math-218 is arbitrary. We denote the set of all dimensions c06-math-219 by Q. The d-dimensional row vector of poverty thresholds or threshold limits in different dimensions is the vector c06-math-220. The notion of vulnerability we consider, in this section, is a multidimensional distress in the sense that the affected person faces descending trend of dimensional achievements. More precisely, there are downside risks that the individual's achievements in different dimensions drop down to levels lower than the corresponding thresholds.

For any dimension j, there are c06-math-221 states of nature, and the set of such states is designated by c06-math-222, c06-math-223. Since different dimensions reflect different aspects of well-being, it is unlikely that the types and numbers of states will be the same across dimensions. Let c06-math-224 and c06-math-225 stand, respectively, for person i's achievement in state s of dimension j and the probability of appearance of c06-math-226; c06-math-227, c06-math-228. Evidently, c06-math-229 and c06-math-230 for all c06-math-231 and c06-math-232.

The c06-math-233 dimensional row vector of returns for person i from dimension j and the corresponding probability vector are given, respectively, by c06-math-234 and c06-math-235. For any c06-math-236, each triplet c06-math-237 is an element of c06-math-238, where c06-math-239 is that subset of the positive part of the real line in which c06-math-240 can vary. More precisely, for any c06-math-241, c06-math-242, where c06-math-243 and c06-math-244 are arbitrary. Given that there are d dimensions of well-being, for any c06-math-245, a multidimensional vulnerable situation is of the form c06-math-246. Let c06-math-247 stand for the set of all multidimensional vulnerable situations for person i, that is, c06-math-248.

We follow the union method of identification in this multidimensional framework, that is, person i is called multidimensionally vulnerable if there is at least one dimension j and one state c06-math-249 such that c06-math-250 and c06-math-251. Let c06-math-252 be the vector of censored returns for person i from different states in dimension j, where c06-math-253, with c06-math-254 and c06-math-255 being arbitrary. We similarly symbolize c06-math-256 by c06-math-257.

The extent of destitution felt by person i in state c06-math-258 is measured by the deprivation indicator c06-math-259, which we designate by c06-math-260, for short; c06-math-261, c06-math-262. The vector c06-math-263 stands for the vector of such indicators associated with c06-math-264. For any person c06-math-265, the expected poverty in dimension j corresponding to c06-math-266 is c06-math-267, where the transformed deprivation indicator c06-math-268 satisfying c06-math-269 is continuous, decreasing, and strictly convex in state-contingent returns. For any c06-math-270 and c06-math-271, c06-math-272 is based on the returns censored at c06-math-273 .

The task of a multidimensional vulnerability index c06-math-274 for person i is to summarize the information contained in the multidimensional vulnerable situation of the type c06-math-275 for the person in terms of a nonnegative real number. Hence, the domain of the nonnegative real-valued function c06-math-276 is c06-math-277. More precisely, c06-math-278.

Most of the individualistic axioms suggested in the earlier section, for a one-dimensional individual vulnerability index, can be adapted in the multidimensional system under certain alterations in the statements. For the sake of completeness, next we state these axioms analytically.

  1. State-Restricted Weak Focus: For any c06-math-279, if for all c06-math-280, c06-math-281, c06-math-282, then c06-math-283, where c06-math-284, c06-math-285, c06-math-286 for all c06-math-287; c06-math-288 for all c06-math-289, c06-math-290; and for any c06-math-291, c06-math-292.
  2. State-Restricted Strong Focus: For any c06-math-293, if for some c06-math-294, c06-math-295, c06-math-296, then c06-math-297, where c06-math-298, c06-math-299, c06-math-300 for all c06-math-301; c06-math-302 for all c06-math-303, c06-math-304; and for any c06-math-305, c06-math-306.
  3. State-Restricted Monotonicity: For any c06-math-307 if for some c06-math-308, c06-math-309, c06-math-310, c06-math-311, then c06-math-312, where c06-math-313, c06-math-314, c06-math-315 for all c06-math-316; c06-math-317 for all c06-math-318, c06-math-319; and for any c06-math-320, c06-math-321.
  4. Across-States Transfer: For any c06-math-322 if for some c06-math-323; c06-math-324, c06-math-325, then c06-math-326, where c06-math-327, c06-math-328, c06-math-329, where c06-math-330; c06-math-331 for all c06-math-332, c06-math-333; and for any c06-math-334, c06-math-335.
  5. State-Restricted Monotonicity in Threshold Limits: For any c06-math-336, if for at least one c06-math-337, c06-math-338 and c06-math-339, then c06-math-340, where, c06-math-341, c06-math-342, for all c06-math-343 and c06-math-344.
  6. Severity of Downside Risks: For any c06-math-345 if for some c06-math-346, c06-math-347, then c06-math-348, where c06-math-349, c06-math-350, c06-math-351; c06-math-352 for all c06-math-353; c06-math-354 for all c06-math-355, c06-math-356; and for any c06-math-357, c06-math-358.
  7. State-Restricted Boundedness: The index c06-math-359 is bounded between 0 and 1, where the lower bound is achieved if for c06-math-360, c06-math-361 for all c06-math-362, c06-math-363 and c06-math-364. c06-math-365 reaches its upper bound if for c06-math-366, c06-math-367 for all c06-math-368, c06-math-369 and c06-math-370, assuming that this case of maximal deprivation is well defined.
  8. Continuity in State-Contingent Returns: For given probability vectors and threshold limits, c06-math-371 varies continuously in state-contingent returns, assuming that the vulnerability status of the person remains unchanged.

For a given profile of probability vectors and vector of threshold limits, if a person is not deprived in any state of any dimension, then giving him more return in some state of some arbitrary dimension should not have any impact on his vulnerability. The state-restricted weak focus axiom demands this. The remaining axioms stated in the section are simple multivariate translations, involving states of nature in different dimensions, of univariate vulnerability axioms specified in Section 6.2. Our discussion on postulates for the one-dimensional indices applies equally well here under obvious modifications.

An example of an individual vulnerability index in this multidimensional framework can be

where c06-math-373 is arbitrary and c06-math-374. Here the expression c06-math-375 can be regarded as expected poverty from dimension j ascertained by the Bourguignon–Chakravarty multidimensional vulnerability index for person i. The parametric restrictions c06-math-376 and c06-math-377 are sufficient to guarantee that c06-math-378 agrees with all the axioms laid down for an arbitrary c06-math-379.

For defining an aggregate multidimensional vulnerability index for a given set of population c06-math-380 with n individuals, we denote the arbitrary vulnerable situation c06-math-381 by c06-math-382, or, by c06-math-383 (for short), where c06-math-384 and c06-math-385. Further, let c06-math-386 stand for a multidimensional global vulnerable situation c06-math-387. The set of all multidimensional global vulnerable situations is c06-math-388. Let c06-math-389 stand for the d dimensional vector c06-math-390 corresponding to c06-math-391, where c06-math-392 is person i's expected poverty in dimension j.

The arithmetic average of individual multidimensional vulnerability indices can now be taken as an index of the aggregate multidimensional vulnerability index. Accordingly, for any arbitrary population size of c06-math-393, this global index c06-math-394 is defined as

where c06-math-396 is arbitrary for each i and c06-math-397 fulfills the axioms stated in the section.

A clear distinction exists between the aggregation rule employed in (6.8) and the dashboard and composite index approaches. As we have observed, different dimensional indices of deprivation (or well-being) can be assembled in a set, framing the dashboard approach. On the other hand, when the dimensional indices are united, using some aggregator, we have a composite index. It may be recalled here that one common problem with dashboards and composite indices is that they ignore joint distributions of deprivations or well-beings.

Observe that in (6.7) statewise deprivations of person i in a dimension are aggregated initially. The aggregated dimension level figures are clubbed together to arrive at c06-math-398. Then in (6.8), we have a vector of individual multidimensional indices c06-math-399 that are combined using the unweighted arithmetic averaging criterion. By construction, joint distribution of deprivations across the dimensions is explicitly taken into account.

In view of satisfaction of population subgroup decomposability by c06-math-400, its policy applicability for pinpointing population subgroups that are distressed more by multidimensional vulnerability is evident. Several attractive features of this aggregate vulnerability index c06-math-401 are analyzed next.

  1. i. It reaches the lower bound 0 when everybody is nondeprived in all states of different dimensions. In contrast, it arrives at the upper bound 1 if all the persons are maximally deprived in all the dimensions.
  2. ii. It is continuous in achievement quantities under certain mild conditions.
  3. iii. Because of increasingness in individual arguments c06-math-402, where c06-math-403, it is strongly monotonic. Therefore, any change in an individual index, as desired by the axioms, specified earlier, is taken into account by the index properly.
  4. iv. It also fulfills a multidimensional regressive transfer principle, which we define next.

In the aforementioned definition, given that all the probability distributions and the threshold limits are the same across the profiles c06-math-424 and c06-math-425 , we can say that c06-math-426 is obtained from c06-math-427 by a regressive transfer of achievement in state c06-math-428 from person h to person i. In c06-math-429, person h, the donor of the transfer, has higher deprivation than person i, the transfer recipient, in state s of dimension j, and the corresponding positive downside risk is also not lower for the donor. This regressive transfer of achievement in state s of dimension j makes the donor more deprived in the state, where c06-math-430 , c06-math-431 and c06-math-432 are arbitrary. Both the numbers of dimensions and the corresponding states for which (i) and (ii) hold can be more than 1. Accordingly, it is a multidimensional phenomenon. Given that the donor has at least a high positive downside risk than the recipient in the state under consideration, the regressive transfer that generates c06-math-433 from c06-math-434 should increase vulnerability.

To get more insights into this definition, let c06-math-435, c06-math-436, c06-math-437, and c06-math-438. Assume that c06-math-439, c06-math-440, c06-math-441, c06-math-442; c06-math-443, c06-math-444, c06-math-445, and c06-math-446. In state 3 of dimension 2, person 2 has a higher deprivation but lower probability than person 1. Therefore, a regressive transfer between the two persons in state 3 of dimension 2 is ruled out. Since in state 1 of the dimension, the two persons are equally deprived, a regressive transfer is not possible here as well. Finally, in state 2 of the dimension, person 1 is not deprived but person 2 is deprived. In consequence, this state does not come under the purview of a transfer. Continuing this way, we can identify that only in state 3 of dimension 1, a regressive transfer from person 2 to person 1 is permissible.

The following axiom can now be stated formally:

  1. Multidimensional Vulnerability Regressive Transfer: If the multidimensional global vulnerable situation c06-math-447 is obtained from the situation c06-math-448 by a multidimensional regressive transfer, c06-math-449.
  1. v. Given that the index is simple unweighted average of individual multidimensional vulnerability indices, it is a symmetric function of individual indices. In other words, this postulate states that any permutation of individual vulnerability extents keeps its value unchanged.
  2. vi. Since the index is defined as the average of individual multidimensional vulnerability indices, it remains unaltered under replications of the population.

Even though properties scrutinized in (i)–(vi) are specified for the subgroup decomposable index c06-math-450, they can be taken as intuitively reasonable postulates for a general multidimensional vulnerability index c06-math-451, which may not be subgroup decomposable.

As an example of a multidimensional vulnerability index at the society level, we may suggest the use of the following:

where for any c06-math-453, c06-math-454; c06-math-455 and c06-math-456. Equation (6.9) can be rewritten in terms of individual expected poverties c06-math-457 for different dimensions as

6.10 equation

The subgroup decomposable Bourguignon–Chakravarty multidimensional vulnerability to poverty index c06-math-459 , encompassing the whole population, is bounded between 0 and 1, strongly monotonic, symmetric, population replication invariant, and correctly responsive to the multidimensional vulnerability regressive transfer principle for all c06-math-460 and c06-math-461. (See properties stated in (i)–(vi) earlier.)

6.4 Concluding Remarks

In this chapter, we have only addressed the problem of representing a vulnerable situation, formulated in a particular way, numerically. In a recent paper, Chakravarty et al. (2015) developed a vulnerability ordering that regards one situation (e.g., agriculture) as not less vulnerable than another (say, fisheries) if and only if the former does not have lower level of vulnerability than the latter for a family of expected poverty indices, assuming that income is the only dimension of well-being. The family includes expected poverty indices, where the underlying transformed deprivation indicators are continuous, normalized, and convex. While such indicators we have discussed in Section 6.2 are homogeneous of degree 0 in the state-level returns and the threshold limit, the ordering does not require this property. Expected poverty indices with translation invariant transformed deprivation indicators that remain unchanged under equal absolute changes in such returns and the threshold limit can as well be included in this family. An example of such a function is the Zheng (2000) transformed deprivation function defined by c06-math-462, where c06-math-463 is a constant. This function is decreasing, continuous, and strictly convex in state-dependent returns below the threshold limit. The main result developed by Chakravarty et al. (2015) does not require equality of the number of states across the situations. It banks explicitly on Blackwell's (1951, 1953) well-known results for comparisons of experiments (see also Cremer, 1982 and Leshno and Spector, 1992). A novelty of this ordering is that it can be regarded as vulnerability analog to the Hardy et al. (1934) classical result on the measurement of inequality. Hardeweg et al. (2013) considered a stochastic dominance-based partial ordering in this context. The multidimensional extension of these orderings is an issue of a natural investigation here. We have also not incorporated ordinally measurable dimensions into our analysis. Research on axiomatic approach to vulnerability has just begun. Many more relevant aspects are yet to be explored.

In a recent contribution, Chakravarty et al. (2016) investigated the implications of vulnerability on the income poverty line. More accurately, the problem of adapting the income poverty threshold under vulnerability so that the adjusted poverty line also represents the subsistence standard of living in a situation of vulnerability has been addressed. The central idea underlying this process of modification is that the individual utility derived from the existing poverty line and the expected utility generated by the new poverty line affected by a random error (noise) indicating vulnerability are the same. Consequently, the formulation relies on the implicit assumption that the vulnerability is treated as a low expected utility situation. Under certain sensible assumptions about the noise, in an additive model, the harmonized poverty line is shown to exceed the existing poverty line by a constant amount if the utility function possesses constant Arrow–Pratt absolute risk aversion. Likewise, in a multiplicative model, the adjusted poverty line becomes a scale transformation of the existing poverty line, where the underlying scalar is greater than unity, if the utility function exhibits constant Arrow–Pratt relative risk aversion. (The relative risk aversion measure is obtained by multiplying its absolute counterpart by income.) An empirical illustration of the developed methodology has been provided using data from the Asia-Pacific region. Clearly, an extension of this approach to the multidimensional setup will require consideration of joint distribution of the noise term representing vulnerability.

In an earlier contribution, Dang and Lanjouw (2014) developed two formal approaches to the determination of the vulnerability line. According to the first approach, for a population subgroup that is clearly not vulnerable, the vulnerability line has been defined as the lower-bound income of subgroup. In contrast, in the second approach, a subgroup that is not poor currently but faces a real risk of falling into poverty is considered. The upper-bound income for this subgroup has been taken as the vulnerability line. While essential to the Chakravarty et al. (2016) approach is the Arrow–Pratt theory of risk aversion, the Dang–Lanjouw approach relies on a probabilistic formulation.

In Chapter 5, we have assumed perfect foresight of period-by-period achievements on different dimensions for all the individuals. In their highly interesting contribution, Calvo and Dercon (2009) suggested one-dimensional statistic of vulnerability in a dynamic world in which the assumption of realization of incomes in the future periods with certainty is relaxed. Let c06-math-464 stand for person i's income when state c06-math-465 materializes in period t, where c06-math-466 denotes the set of states of nature in period c06-math-467 and c06-math-468. We write c06-math-469 for the corresponding censored income. Let c06-math-470 be the probability that state c06-math-471 in period t emerges. Evidently, for all c06-math-472 and c06-math-473, c06-math-474. The expected value of transformed normalized (censored) incomes in period t is c06-math-475, where c06-math-476 is a constant (see Eq. (6.1)), E denotes the expected value operator, and z is the income poverty line.

The authors proposed the use of the following modified version of (5.12)

6.11 equation

as a forward-looking and dynamic metric of poverty, where c06-math-478 is the profile of the vectors of person i's incomes associated with different sates of nature in all T periods, c06-math-479 is the corresponding profile of probability vectors, and c06-math-480 is the rate of time discounting. This index can be regarded as a representation of upcoming intertemporal individual poverty because it is not based on evaluation of poverty for a single period; instead, it takes into account poverty assessments for a sequence of forthcoming periods in a world of uncertainty. According to the authors, “one of the contributions of this paper is to identify the Chakravarty poverty index as the best choice if the poverty analysis moves from static poverty on to vulnerability” (Calvo and Dercon, 2009, p. 57). Clearly, this index can be employed for arriving at a complete ordering of different possible paths of standard of living, judged by utilizing future uncertain incomes. A natural generalization of this nice proposal with many innovative features is to develop analogous quantifiers in the multidimensional setup.

References

  1. Amin, S., A.S. Rai, and G. Topa. 2003. Does Microcredit Reach the Poor and Vulnerable? Evidence from Northern Bangladesh. Journal of Development Economics 70: 59–82.
  2. Arrow, K.J. 1965. Aspects of the Theory of Risk Bearing. Helsinki: Yrjo Jahnssonin Saatio.
  3. Basu, K. and P. Nolen. 2005. Vulnerability, Unemployment and Poverty: A New Class of Measures, its Axiomatic Properties and Applications. BREAD Working Paper 38.
  4. Binswanger, H.P. 1981. Attitudes Toward Risk: Theoretical Implications of an Experiment in Rural India. Economic Journal 91: 867–890.
  5. Blackwell, D. 1951. Comparison of Experiments. Proceedings of the Second Berkeley Symposium on Mathematical Statistics and Probability. Berkeley: University of California Press, 93–102.
  6. Blackwell, D. 1953. Equivalent Comparisons of Experiments. Annals of Mathematical Statistics 24: 265–272.
  7. Bourguignon, F. and S.R. Chakravarty.2003. The Measurement of Multidimensional Poverty. Journal of Economic Inequality 1: 25–49.
  8. Calvo, C. 2008. Vulnerability to Multidimensional Poverty: Peru, 1998–2002. World Development 36: 1011–1020.
  9. Calvo S. and S. Dercon. 2009. Chronic Poverty and All that: The Measurement of Poverty over Time. In T. Addison, D. Hulme, and R. Kanbur (eds.) Poverty Dynamics: Interdisciplinary Perspectives. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 29–58.
  10. Calvo, C. and S. Dercon. 2013. Vulnerability of Individual and Aggregate Poverty. Social Choice and Welfare 41: 721–740.
  11. Chakravarty, S.R. 1983. A New Index of Poverty. Mathematical Social Sciences 6: 307–313.
  12. Chakravarty, S.R. and N. Chattopadhyay.2015. Measuring Vulnerability to Poverty: An Expected Poverty Approach. In S. Guha, R.P. Kundu, and S. Subramanian (eds.) Contributions to Economic Analysis: Essays in Honor of Satish Jain. London: Routledge, 313–323.
  13. Chakravarty, S.R., N. Chattopadhyay, and L. Qingbin. 2015. Vulnerability Orderings for Expected Poverty Indices. Japanese Economic Review 66: 300–310.
  14. Chakravarty, S.R., N. Chattopadhyay, J. Silber, and G. Wan. 2016. Measuring the Impact of Vulnerability on the Number of Poor: A New Methodology with Empirical Illustration. In J. Silber and G. Wan, 84–117.
  15. Chaudhuri, S. 2003. Assessing Vulnerability to Poverty: Concepts, Empirical Methods and Illustrative Examples. Mimeographed, Columbia University.
  16. Chaudhuri, S., J. Jalan, and A. Suryahadi. 2002. Assessing Household Vulnerability to Poverty from Cross-section Data: A Methodology and Estimates from Indonesia. Discussion Paper Series 0102-52, Department of Economics, Columbia University.
  17. Christiaensen, L. and R. Boisvert. 2000. On Measuring Household Food Vulnerability: Case Evidence from Northern Mali. Working Paper 2000-5. Department of Agricultural, Resource and Managerial Economics, Cornell University.
  18. Christiaensen, L. and K. Subbarao. 2005. Towards an Understanding of Household Vulnerability in Rural Kenya. Journal of African Economies 14: 520–558.
  19. Coudouel, A. and J. Hentschel. 2000. Poverty Data and Measurement. Preliminary Draft for a Sourcebook on Poverty Reduction Strategies. Washington DC: The World Bank.
  20. Cremer, J. 1982. A Simple Proof of Blackwell's “Comparison of Experiments' Theorem”. Journal of Economic Theory 27: 439–444.
  21. Dang, H.H. and P.F. Lanjouw. 2014. Two Definitions of a Vulnerability Line and their Empirical Application. Policy Research Working Paper No. 6944. Washington, DC: World Bank.
  22. Dercon, S. 2002. Income Risk, Coping Strategies and Safety Nets. World Bank Research Observer 17: 141–166.
  23. Dercon, S. and P. Krishnan.2000. Vulnerability, Seasonality and Poverty in Ethiopia. Journal of Development Studies 36: 25–53.
  24. Dutta, I., J.E. Foster, and A. Mishra. 2011. On Measuring Vulnerability to Poverty. Social Choice and Welfare 37: 743–761.
  25. Elbers, C. and J.W. Gunning. 2003. Vulnerability in a Stochastic Dynamic Model. Mimeographed, Tinbergen Institute.
  26. Foster, J.E., J. Greer, and E. Thorbecke. 1984. A Class of Decomposable Poverty Measures. Econometrica 52: 761–766.
  27. Fujii, T. 2016. Vulnerability: A Review of Literature. In J. Silber and G. Wan, 53–83.
  28. Gaiha, R. and K. Imai. 2009. Measuring Vulnerability and Poverty: Estimates for Rural India. In I.W. Naudé, A. Santos-Paulino, and M. McGillivray (eds.) Vulnerability in Developing Countries. Tokyo: United Nations University Press, 13–54.
  29. Glewwe, P. and G. Hall. 1998. Are Some Groups More Vulnerable to Macroeconomic Shocks than Others? Hypothesis Tests Based on Panel Data from Peru. Journal of Development Economics 56: 181–206.
  30. Günther, I. and K. Harttgen. 2009. Estimating Household Vulnerability to Idiosyncratic and Covariance Shocks: A Novel Method Applied in Madagascar. World Development 37: 1222–1234.
  31. Hardeweg, B., A. Wagner, and H. Waibel. 2013. A Distributional Approach Comparing Vulnerability applied to Rural Provinces in Thailand and Vietnam. Journal of Asian Economics 25: 53–65.
  32. Hardy, G.H., J.E. Littlewood, and G. Polya. 1934. Inequalities. New York: Cambridge University Press.
  33. Hoddinott, J. and A. Quisumbing. 2003. Methods for Micro-Econometric Risk and Vulnerability Assessments. Social Protection Discussion Paper 0324. Washington, DC: World Bank.
  34. Holzmann R. and S. Jorgensen. 1999. Social Protection as Social Risk Management: Conceptual Underpinnings for the Social Protection Sector Strategy Paper. Social Protection Discussion Paper 9904. Washington, DC: World Bank.
  35. Hoogeveen, J., E. Tesliuc, R. Vakis, and S. Dercon. 2004. A Guide to Analysis of Risk, Vulnerability and Vulnerable Groups. Policy Research Working Paper. Washington, DC: World Bank.
  36. Kamanou, G. and J. Morduch. 2002. Measuring Vulnerability to Poverty. WIDER Discussion Paper, 2002/58.
  37. Kamanou, G. and J. Morduch. 2004. Measuring Vulnerability to Poverty. In S. Dercon (ed.) Insurance Against Poverty. New York: Oxford University Press, 155–175.
  38. Klasen, S. and F. Povel. 2013. Defining and Measuring Vulnerability: State of the Art and New Proposals. In S. Klasen and H. Waibel (eds.) Vulnerability to Poverty: Theory, Measurement and Determinants. London: Palgrave–Macmillan, 17–47.
  39. Leshno, M. and Y. Spector. 1992. An Elementary Proof of Blackwell's Theorem. Mathematical Social Sciences 25: 95–98.
  40. Ligon, E. and L. Schechter. 2003. Measuring Vulnerability. Economic Journal 113: C95–C102.
  41. López-Calva, L.F. and E. Ortiz-Juarez.2014. A Vulnerability Approach to the Definition of the Middle Class. Journal of Economic Inequality 12: 23–47.
  42. Morduch, J. 1994. Poverty and Vulnerability. American Economic Review: Papers and Proceedings 84: 221–225.
  43. Pratt, J.W. 1964. Risk Aversion in the Small and the Large. Econometrica 32: 122–136.
  44. Pritchett, L., A. Suryahadi, and S. Sumarto. 2000. Quantifying Vulnerability to Poverty: A Proposed Measure, with Application to Indonesia. Social Monitoring and Early Response Unit Working Paper. Washington, DC: World Bank.
  45. Ravallion, M. 1988. Expected Poverty under Risk-`Induced Welfare Variability. Economic Journal 98: 1171–1182.
  46. Rothschild, M. and J.E. Stiglitz. 1970. Increasing Risk: I. A Definition. Journal of Economic Theory 2: 225–243.
  47. Sen, A.K. 1999. A Plan for Asia's Growth: Build on Much that is Good in the ‘Eastern Strategy’. Asia Week, October 8, 25(40). Available at: http://edition.cnn.com/ASIANOW/asiaweek/magazine/99/1008/viewpoint.html.
  48. Silber, J. and G. Wan. (eds.) 2016. The Asian Poverty Miracle: Impressive Accomplishments or Incomplete Achievements? Northampton: Edward Elgar, Forthcoming.
  49. Skoufias, E. and A.R. Quisumbing. 2005. Consumption Insurance and Vulnerability to Poverty: A Synthesis of Evidence from Bangladesh, Ethiopia, Mali, Mexico and Russia. European Journal of Development Research 17: 24–58.
  50. Suryahadi, A. and S. Sumarto. 2003. Poverty and Vulnerability in Indonesia Before and After the Economic Crisis. Asian Economic Journal 17: 45–64.
  51. Townsend, R. 1994. Risk and Insurance in Village India. Econometrica 62: 539–591.
  52. Watts, H.W. 1968. An Economic Definition of Poverty. In D.P. Moynihan (ed.) On Understanding of Poverty. New York: Basic Books, 316–319.
  53. World Bank. 1997. Identifying the Vulnerable: New Evidence from Peru, Poverty Lines, A Joint Publication by the Policy Research and Social Policy Departments. Washington, DC: World Bank. Available at: http://web.worldbank.org/archive/website00002/WEB/PDF/PL_N06.PDF.
  54. Zheng, B. 2000. Minimum Distribution Sensitivity, Poverty Aversion, and Poverty Orderings. Journal of Economic Theory 95: 116–137.
..................Content has been hidden....................

You can't read the all page of ebook, please click here login for view all page.
Reset
3.143.4.181