27  Human security and personal responsibilities in light of climate change defeatism and complacency

Thomas Heyd

Introduction

The concept of human security, as elaborated by GECHS,1 concerns ‘the freedom to take actions that promote wellbeing in response to changing environmental conditions’ (emphasis added, Lonergan et al., 2000). More specifically, human security is closely linked to norms, values, rights and entitlements and it draws attention to notions of empowerment, protection and responsibilities. It is about fulfilling people’s vital freedoms and the development of capacities to create satisfying lives for all people (O’Brien et al., 2010).

Human security, in other words, entails not only an end state, described in terms of an increase in wellbeing and a decrease in exposure to certain threats, but also a particular process of achieving this end state, namely, the active participation of individuals and communities in achieving this end state. As such, the definition of human security is explicitly normative in a double sense, since it makes reference to both ends and means. It also explicitly calls upon individuals as well as society at large to take responsibility concerning problematic environmental conditions, such as may be expected from climate change.

Indeed, there are good reasons to believe that individuals as well as societies have responsibilities to act on climate change. Paradoxically, knowledge of the increasing certainty about human-induced climate change, and of the severe harm that it may bring to large portions of the world population, may lead individuals and communities to fall into a paralysing defeatism. Such defeatism, furthermore, may be accompanied by complacency, due to the assumption that, given our societies’ institutional, scientific and technical capabilities, we can simply wait to address the problems posed by climate change until they actually become troublesome in our proximate, local, environment.

Here, I begin by explaining a little further the grounds for taking responsibility concerning climate change. After this, I point out that defeatist and complacent attitudes may interfere with acting on our responsibilities, thereby possibly leading to failure in the application of entirely feasible mitigation and adaptation measures. Next, I note that the result may be significantly greater economic costs and human and ecological harms than would otherwise be incurred. I close by pointing toward some of the ways to address these problematic attitudes, and propose that individuals who are aware of this situation should perceive it as a call to help transform the socio-cultural conditions that generate them.

Prudential and ethical responsibilities

A diversity of measures, undertaken by various levels of governments, coordinated nationally and internationally, are doubtlessly necessary in order to create the institutional framework and material infrastructures, and to set the overall course for society, to address climate change satisfactorily through reduction of greenhouse gas emissions, as well as other mitigating strategies, and through adaptation to already inevitable effects (Nihlén Fahlquist, 2009).2 Though responsibility for action on climate change generally has been discussed in relation to the duties of particular nation-states or blocks of nations (the West or Global North vs. the ‘developing’ nations of the Global South and the ‘emerging’ BRIC (Brazil, Russia, India and China) countries), there are good reasons to also consider the responsibilities for action of individual citizens, because of their important role in bringing about change in society (see, e.g., Moser, 2007). Active involvement by concerned citizens is crucial in several respects: as sources of new civil society initiatives, as pressure on governmental institutions to carry through on measures proposed, and as proof of the realisability of the collective transformation of current patterns of production and consumption.

The Fourth Assessment Report of the Intergovernmental Panel on Climate Change (IPCC, 2007) strongly supports the view that climate change processes are accelerating, and that future as well as present generations are going to experience very significant increases in severity of disastrous, and possibly catastrophic, phenomena associated with rapid environmental change, which will bring about significant economic costs and harm to human and non-human beings. Alarmingly, measured trends in the rise in global average temperatures and sea levels are seen to be even exceeding the worst-case scenarios of this latest IPCC Report.

One analysis of recent developments, published in PNAS, states that (2000– 2006) trends in the growth in greenhouse gas emissions due to increased economic activity, greater carbon intensity, and lowered efficiency of natural sinks ‘characterize a carbon cycle that is generating stronger-than-expected climate forcing sooner than expected’ (Canadell et al., 2007:18869, also see Chen et al. 2011 on faster than expected range shifts of species due to climate change). Based on such observations, Will Steffen concludes in a 2009 report for the Australian Government that ‘risks associated with the upper range of the IPCC projections of climate change for this century need to be considered seriously’ (Steffen, 2009: 4). Most recently it has been found that ‘Recent temperature measurements show that the Arctic is warming twice as fast as the rest of the planet, with sea ice this summer shrinking to its smallest extent on record’ (D’Andrea et al., 2012).

So, given that in the middle to long run everyone, and his or her descendants, can be expected to be at risk from at least some of the harmful effects of climate change, a strong case can already be made for taking personal responsibility for reasons of prudence. This by itself means that, reasonably, those individuals who are capable of it should actively support measures directed at mitigation and adaptation, to be implemented both locally and globally across societies and geographical boundaries, and possibly should go even further and develop initiatives to mobilise society about the impending peril (see Garvey, 2008).

There are also very good reasons for supposing that addressing climate change should be considered a matter of ethical responsibility. These reasons are diverse, and have been discussed in detail elsewhere (see Gardiner, 2004; Garvey, 2008). They range from taking responsibility for the harmful effects that one causes, to fairness in distribution of burdens; and from assuming responsibility on the basis of a commitment to a general harm prevention principle, to the humanitarian requirements of solidarity with the more vulnerable. I explain these reasons a bit further here.

Of particular relevance in this discussion is the fact that the industrialised countries have produced most of the anthropogenic greenhouse gases now in circulation, and continue to do so at accelerating rates. This means that they bear a special responsibility from the point of view of justice for the harm that these greenhouse gas accumulations in the atmosphere produce (this may be seen as an application of the ‘polluter pays’ principle). Moreover, insofar as responsibility can be shared across all those who in some way benefit from, or uphold, a system that causes harm, not just governments but anyone who lives in the Global North, and is a beneficiary of the industrial development brought about by historical greenhouse gas emissions, bears a responsibility for the harmful effects of climate change (Young, 2006), and ought to actively support mitigation and adaptation strategies.

One may also consider common principles of fairness, which, when applied to the capacity to act on urgent matters of common concern, translate into the principle that those who are more capable of acting should do more (Garvey, 2008). With regard to climate change, this approach means that those who are better off should assume greater responsibility to reduce fossil fuel consumption and contribute more, proportionally, to mitigation and adaptation strategies than those who have fewer means.

Notably, insofar as the financial, technological and organisational capital accumulated by industrialised nations largely has been built from, or with the help of, the resources of the rest of the world, and since a small fraction of this capital would likely be sufficient to soften the impact of climate change for poorer populations, there is, moreover, reason for supposing that, in fairness, the richer countries, and especially the richer individuals who live there, have an important responsibility to assist the poorer in the implementation of adaptation strategies. Importantly, some adaptation strategies also may make the poorer more vulnerable if not carried out in full consultation with, or under the direction of, those most in need.

Another approach to the question of ethical responsibility draws on the supposition that those who can prevent harm from occurring ought to do so, out of consideration for the ultimately common condition of vulnerability that we share as human beings (this may be expressed more fully as a general harm prevention principle, Singer, 1979, or as a principle of respect for persons, see Kant, 1785/2002, or as a principle of solidarity). Everyday examples include acts, such as saving a child from being accidentally run over by a speeding car, or rescuing a person from drowning in a nearby pool, but also helping people from dying due to malnutrition, when doing so does not require sacrificing anything of comparable moral value. This means that those of us who are relatively well-off ought to actively address the new risks to present and future human (and possibly to non-human) beings brought on by climate change.

As such, these various ways of thinking of responsibility with regard to climate change, in terms of justice, harm prevention and solidarity, require commitment with those who are more vulnerable and converge on the idea of taking responsibility for human security, since it concerns the promotion of wellbeing in the context of rapid environmental change. Insofar as the idea of human security not only focuses on the end state to be achieved but also on protecting and advancing options and capacities, ‘necessary to end, mitigate or adapt to threats to people’s human, environmental and social rights’ (Lonergan et al., 2000), it also highlights the importance of the capacity to act according to one’s own judgement, which is an expression of autonomy.

The ability to direct one’s own life according to one’s own choices, in addition to various other rights, is widely considered a key ingredient in the ultimate good for human beings, and, as such, is part of the intrinsic value of our lives. In other words, the idea of human security makes clear that, insofar as climate change is a threat, not only to health, life and livelihood, but also to the ability of people to actively respond to such threats according to their own choices, it constitutes a very significant reason to act on the prudential and ethical responsibilities that arise from this process.

Some may object, however, that, even granting any of the ethical principles suggested, citizens should rather focus on other issues that supposedly are more urgent than climate change. Someone may ask, for example, why we should invest in mitigation and adaptation while nearly a billion people around the world are malnourished.3 Similarly, one may ask why finding safe storage for rapidly growing quantities of health-threatening nuclear wastes, which can be radioactive for more than a million years, should not take precedence. Or, why the question of nuclear weapons proliferation should not come first. Or, why the achievement of peace among nuclear armed countries in volatile areas, in the Middle East, the border regions of Afghanistan-Pakistan, Pakistan-India, or India-China, should not take priority (see Homer-Dixon, 2006, for discussion of a ‘watchlist’ of global stresses).

The key argument in response to such objections is that climate change likely will make most other urgent problems even more urgent. As is well-known, a large portion of the world population is vulnerable to food scarcity, droughts, flooding and other effects associated with climate change, and has very limited resilience with which to recover after disastrous incidents. Historically, it is well known, moreover, that environmental factors (be they cold spells or droughts) are often exploited in conflictual situations (see, e.g., Fagan, 2000).

Consequently, food insecurity, safe storage of nuclear wastes in a politically fragile world, the threat of the use of nuclear weapons, the potential for armed conflicts, and so on, are all issues that potentially can become much more problematic when accompanied by climate change. Any further delay in committing to thorough-going mitigation and adaptation will foreseeably make many other upcoming problems so much harder to cope with, thereby making climate change an issue that is at least as urgent as any other. So, in response to the objection that other matters are more urgent, one may say that, due to the ‘multiplier effects’ that it entails, climate change constitutes an especially important issue to immediately address.

Another objection may be that the call to action on climate change may seem unrealistic, given the priorities of today’s world (such as resolving the current economic crisis). There are, moreover, various types of obstacles for people to make their action effective in terms of carbon reductions that individuals face at the psychological level (see Gifford, 2008; American Psychology Association, 2009), at the informational level (insofar as people often do not know what to do, see Wolf, 2010), and at the societal-systemic level (insofar as action by individuals is limited by the range of choices available as determined by society at large).

In response to these objections one may note that, though, depending on individual circumstances, it may be difficult to quickly transform agriculture, industry or transportation on a societal or planetary scale, there may be a few things that most people can undertake to get the transformation of our societies started. For example, those who are fairly well-off can take steps to eat, heat, transport, work and build with renewable types of energy, and to re-use, recycle, return and compost used materials. For all of these activities there are enough technical solutions and resources available in most places, at least in the industrialised Global North, to get started immediately.

These steps require matching supportive policies from governments, of course. Those with influence in politics, business or the media should be expected to take steps to remind our leaders of their responsibility to change the structural barriers to action, by lobbying governments and uniting in civil society pressure groups. As a matter of fact, there are a variety of real life examples, such as the Transition Town movement, that demonstrate that transformation of the building blocks of society is possible. Consequently, there is little excuse for inaction (even if any adjustment of behaviours requires effort, see Garvey, 2008).

Certainly more detailed arguments for taking seriously our responsibilities (prudential and ethical) can be worked out on the basis of rational choice theory, and from the perspective of diverse approaches to ethics, such as utilitarianism, Kant’s ethics, Rawls’ theory of justice (see Vanderheiden, 2008) or Habermas’ discourse ethics (Habermas, 1991). Similarly, the distribution and source of responsibilities, or the assignment of benefits and costs, may be worth considering in significantly greater detail (e.g., see Gardiner, 2004; Attfield, 2010; Garvey, 2008). In this chapter I will, however, forego further discussion of these matters and assume that it is sufficiently evident that there are good reasons to conclude that climate change constitutes an urgent prudential and ethical issue, such that the need for action, in terms of mitigation and adaptation, is sufficiently well established for well-informed ethical reasoners.

Defeatism and complacency

As noted, climate change has to be addressed through strong policies, laws and incentives issuing from governments and inter-governmental institutions (Nihlén Fahlquist, 2009), but probably little action can be expected from such institutions without active participation by citizens who take personal responsibility for the state of our world. This means, among other things, that it is important to understand how information on climate change is disseminated by natural and social scientists, how it is moulded by the media and appropriated by opinion-makers of various political stripes, and what citizens come to understand as a result of this process (Moser and Dilling, 2007).

Certainly there is no single way in which people apprehend climate news (Moser and Dilling, 2007; Hulme, 2009) but, strikingly, despite widespread awareness of climate change, this knowledge still has not led citizens to exert sufficient pressure on decision-makers to adopt appropriate policies (as we can see from the mostly disappointing series of COP meetings in Copenhagen in 2009, in Cancún in 2010, and in Durban in 2011).4 One of the most troublesome kinds of reaction to increasingly sobering news about accelerating climate change is a kind of ‘all or nothing’ attitude, which proclaims that, since we cannot any longer prevent global warming wholesale, it may be ignored.5 This attitude can constitute a powerful impediment to the implementation of mitigation policies, which, as any other insurance scheme, entails costs up front.

The ‘all or nothing’ attitude seems based on a combination of factual misapprehensions regarding the actual risks associated with further increases in greenhouse gases in the atmosphere (and in the oceans, generating increasing levels of acidification), inappropriate priorities, as well as minimalist habits that recommend inaction despite considerable urgency. Notably, while we are already committed to important climate effects (for example, considerable thawing of on-land glaciers, and increases in droughts and in storm intensities), continued emissions at present rates, however, mean still greater potential commitments, such as the thawing of the Greenland and Antarctica icecaps, with further intensification of linear, as well as hard to fully comprehend non-linear, effects that may be leading to surpassing important tipping points. Therefore, defeatism or ‘fatalism’ in view of climate change may lead to much worse consequences than already are to be expected.

The complementary attitude to the ‘all or nothing’ attitude is to ‘wait and see’ in the expectation that the combined power of science, engineering and financial institutions will be sufficient to cope with national or local disturbances, if and when they occur.6 A complacent ‘wait and see’ attitude, however, fails to take into account key aspects concerning capacity to act (also see O’Brien et al., 2006). The climate science consensus clearly shows that, without adequate mitigation and adaptation strategies to limit the extent of climate change and to lower vulnerability and increase resilience, simple coping cannot and should not be relied upon as a satisfactory response to the severe physical, social and political consequences of climate change (IPCC, 2007; Adger et al., 2009; Schipper and Burton, 2009).

The ‘wait and see’ attitude overlooks that even where societies have considerable scientific capacities, technical know-how and financial power, effective coping with severe environmental events generally requires previous application of these resources through antecedent adaptation strategies. It also overlooks that mitigation may constitute the best kind of adaptation, since mitigation should lead to a significant reduction of the eventual human harm, as well as decrease the financial costs of adaptation, and of the subsequent costs of coping when actual disturbances occur.

A ‘wait and see’ attitude, furthermore, ignores that there are very large populations in the less industrialised parts of the world that lack most of the means to cope with the consequences of climate change, such as increased floods, droughts, and the expected resulting food shortages, greater spread of diseases, and so on. There are, moreover, considerable populations in the industrialised countries, such as poorer urbanites that are homeless or in temporary housing, who are vulnerable to phenomena such as heat waves, severe winter cold, or flooding. There are multiple cases of significant hardship and even mortality caused by such phenomena in Europe and North America, for example, the 2003 European heat wave, the extraordinarily cold European winter of 2009–2010, the 2005 Katrina hurricane and the flooding of New Orleans, as well as the flooding of Genoa, Italy in 2011). Hence, it is reasonable to suppose that, if those who are better-off and have the capability to act forgo vigorous mitigation and adaptation then the more vulnerable will increasingly will be in harm’s way.

Both the defeatist ‘all or nothing’ and the complacent ‘wait and see’ attitudes may lead to unnecessary and supplementary difficulties, and bring about important additional costs, because the problems posed by climate change are taken on too late in the game (see Stern, 2007). These attitudes may, in fact, play into the hands of those who would rather opt for ‘solving’ climate change through costly new geo-engineering mega-projects – even if the solutions proposed are untested and may subject world populations to incalculable new risks (Gardiner, 2010).

Hence, allowing for the development of policy under the sway of either defeatist or complacent attitudes may lead to projects that contravene the precautionary principle (widely endorsed by international law), which demands that populations not be subjected to actions that represent additional levels of risk (see Gardiner, 2004, also see the 1998 Wingspread Statement on the Precautionary Principle). To this we may add that it is to be expected that species extinction rates will accelerate as climate change proceeds, and that coping activities, even if they involve grand schemes to help in the re-location of some threatened species, can do very little to stem this permanent loss of biological diversity.

Summation and conclusion

Insofar as our ethical and prudential responsibilities are supported by a variety of strong reasons that converge on the idea that we have good grounds to concern ourselves with human security, our personal responsibilities include making human security possible. However, both the defeatism of the ‘all or nothing’ attitude, of doing nothing because action supposedly is futile, and the complacency of the ‘wait and see’ attitude, of inaction until coping is inevitable, mean that human and other living beings will be exposed to increasing, very serious, harm, a large part of which is still preventable.

Since addressing climate change will require everybody’s participation (see, e.g., Weber, 2006), these attitudes in society should lead to two questions: how can these attitudes be effectively addressed? and, for individuals who are aware of this situation, what are their responsibilities under these circumstances? Though there is no space here to speak to these questions in depth, with regard to the first question we may note recent research that suggests that such attitudes are the product of a combination of individual, social and material factors, which may be viewed as ‘barriers’ or as ‘obstacles’ to action (see Leiserowitz, 2006; Lorenzoni et al., 2007; Gifford, 2008; Adger et al., 2009; American Psychology Association, 2009).

Notably, defeatist and complacent attitudes may be the result of misapprehensions regarding the facts, troublesome ways of prioritising aims and objectives, or the behaviour-shaping power of problematic habits, all of which together may be the consequences of the dominance of certain unreflected lifestyle choices and common socio-cultural expectations (see, e.g., Lorenzoni et al., 2007). As such, addressing these attitudes calls for measures such as better modes of communication, greater scientific literacy, and more open debate on policy options.

More specifically, the defeatist and complacent attitudes may perhaps be defused by drawing attention to concrete events with local effects, which, as such, are, or may become, available for everyday experience. One way to counter the ‘all or nothing’ attitude, for example, may be by clearly showing that significant additional, local, adaptation costs will have to be incurred by various proximate levels of government if mitigation is not taken on, and that, if adaptation is postponed, coping with severe events will be even more costly. Moreover, to address the ‘wait and see’ attitude it may be useful, for example, to help people recognise that climate change processes are already taking place, including nearby. This may be facilitated through guided tours to nature reserves, where the vertical or latitudinal displacement of species may be observable, or to weather observatories where records of local weather trends are displayed.

Another way to counter these attitudes may consist in creating opportunities for reflection on the fact that vulnerable sectors of our societies, locally and globally, will be directly hurt by climate change. Such facts collide with common humanitarian values that require solidarity with members of the larger community who are at risk, and call for proactive or remedial actions (see, e.g., Heyd, 2007: Chapter 2). Such processes of reflection may help people realise that climate change is an issue of prudential and ethical concern.

With regard to the second question, concerning one’s personal responsibilities under these circumstances, we may note that such responsibilities do not, in any case, disappear in the presence of general inaction. Inaction by society should rather be grounds for renewed creative engagement in strategies that will get other citizens involved. As I have argued elsewhere (Heyd, 2011), insofar as inaction is the result of inadequacies in our cultural frameworks, addressing it may require a fundamental reassessment of these background conditions, which include the basic beliefs, values, habits, practices and lifestyle choices that control our everyday. Consequently, responsibility to act on climate change translates to responsibility to help transform the cultural frameworks that underlie our capacities (or lack of capacities) to take action (see Heyd, 2011). This applies to individuals who understand some of the various barriers and obstacles to action, such as ourselves.

Acknowledgements

I gratefully acknowledge the support of, and valuable discussions at, the Basque Centre for Climate Change (BC3), Bilbao, where I was Research Fellow in May 2011. I also express my appreciation to the School of Environmental Studies, University of Victoria, for providing me with an enriching environment for contextualising my research.

Notes

1  GECHS stands for the Global Environmental Change and Human Security Project of IHDP (International Human Dimensions Programme).

2  Henceforth I will refer to these ways of addressing climate change simply as ‘mitigation and adaptation’.

3  According to the FAO, 868 million people were malnourished in 2010–2012 (FAO, 2012).

4  COP stands for Conference of the Parties (COP17) to the United Nations Framework Convention on Climate Change (UNFCCC).

5  This attitude may even be found among otherwise apparently well-informed people. See Baron (2006: 146), who speaks of ‘a futile war against global warming’, and suggests that it may be more ‘cost-effective’ to devote financial resources to the promotion of the development of poor countries to prepare them for the now inevitable consequences of climate change. There are reasons to be sceptical, in any case, about the value for the poor of many development and adaptation strategies, which primarily benefit already well-to-do minorities. See, for example, Kates (2009).

6  For example, see Baron (2006: 146), who speculates that ‘it may turn out that new technology will make the war against climate change winnable after all’.

References

Adger, W.N., Lorenzoni, I. and O’Brien, K. (eds) (2009) Adapting to Climate Change: Thresholds, Values and Governance, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

American Psychology Association (2009) Psychology and Global Climate Change: Addressing a Multi-faceted Phenomenon and Set of Challenges; A Report by the American Psychological Association’s Task Force on the Interface Between Psychology and Global Climate Change. Online. Available HTTP: http://www.apa.org/science/about/publications/climate-change.aspx (accessed 17 August 2011).

Attfield, R. (2010) ‘Global warming, equity and future generations’, Human Ecology Review, 17 (2): 102–105.

Baron, J. (2006) ‘Thinking about global warming’, Climatic Change, 77: 137–150.

Canadell, J.G., Le Quéré, C., Raupach, M.R., Field, C.B., Buitenhuis, E.T., Ciais, P., Conway, T.J., Gillett, N.P., Houghton, R.A., and Marland, G. (2007) ‘Contributions to accelerating atmospheric CO2 growth from economic activity, carbon intensity, and efficiency of natural sinks’, Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences (PNAS), 104 (47): 18866–18870.

Chen, I-C., Hill, J.K., Ohlemüller, R., Roy, D.B., and Thomas, C.D. (2011) ‘Rapid range shifts of species associated with high levels of climate warming’, Science (19 August), 333 (6045): 1024–1026.

D’Andrea, W.J., Vaillencourt, D.A., Balascio, N.L., Werner, A., Roof, S.R., Retelle, M., and Bradley, R.S. (2012) ‘Mild Little Ice Age and unprecedented recent warmth in an 1800 year lake sediment record from Svalbard’, Geology, published online September 18, 2012.

Fagan, B. (2000) The Little Ice Age: How Climate Made History 1300–1850, New York: Basic Books.

FAO (2012) FAO Hunger Portal, Food and Agriculture Organization. Online. Available HTTP: http://www.fao.org/hunger/en/ (accessed 14 October 2012).

Gardiner, S.M. (2004) ‘Ethics and global climate change’, Ethics, 114: 555–600.

Gardiner, S.M. (2010) ‘Is “arming the future” with geoengineering really the lesser evil?’, in S.M. Gardiner, S. Caney, D. Jamieson, and H. Shue (eds) Climate Ethics, Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Garvey, J. (2008) The Ethics of Climate Change: Right and Wrong in a Warming World, London: Continuum International Publishing Group.

Gifford, R. (2008) ‘Psychology’s essential role in climate change’, Canadian Psychology/Psychologie Canadienne, 49: 273–280.

Habermas, J. (1991) Moral Consciousness and Communicative Action, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

Heyd, T. (2007) Encountering Nature: Toward an Environmental Culture, Aldershot: Ashgate.

Heyd, T. (2011) ‘Ethical and prudential responsibilities, culture and climate change’ in V.P. Nanda (ed) Climate Change and Environmental Ethics, Piscataway, NJ: Transaction Publishers.

Homer-Dixon, T. (2006) The Upside of Down: Catastrophe, Creativity, and the Renewal of Civilization, New York: Knopf/Vintage.

Hulme, M. (2009) Why We Disagree About Climate Change: Understanding Controversy, Inaction and Opportunity, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

IPCC (2007) Climate Change 2007: Synthesis Report, Contribution of Working Groups I, II and III to the Fourth Assessment Report of the Intergovernmental Panel on Climate Change (Core Writing Team, Pachauri, R.K and Reisinger, A. (eds)) Geneva: IPCC.

Kant, I. (1785) Grundlegung zur Metaphysik der Sitten, trans. A.W. Wood (2002) Groundwork for the Metaphysics of Morals, New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.

Kates, R.W. (2009) ‘Cautionary tales: adaptation and the world’s poor’, in L. Schipper and I. Burton (eds), The Earthscan Reader in Adaptation to Climate Change, London: Earthscan.

Leiserowitz, A. (2006) ‘Climate change risk perception and policy preferences: the role of affect, imagery, and values’, Climatic Change, 77: 45–72.

Lonergan, S., with Cocklin, C., Gleditsch, N.P., Langeweg, F., Brklacich, M., Gutierrez-Espeleta, E., Soroos, M., Narain, S. and Matthew, R. (2000) Global Environmental Change and Human Security: Science Plan, Bonn: IHDP Report 11, IHDP: The Global Environmental Change and Human Security Project.

Lorenzoni, I., Nicholson-Cole, S. and Whitmarsh, L. (2007) ‘Barriers perceived to engaging with climate change among the UK public and their policy implications’, Global Environmental Change, 17: 445–459.

Moser, S.C. (2007) ‘More bad news: the risk of neglecting emotional responses to climate change information’, in S.C. Moser and L. Dilling (eds) Creating a Climate for Change, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Moser, S.C. and Dilling, L. (2007) Creating a Climate for Change, Cambridge: Cambridge: University Press.

Nihlén Fahlquist, J.A. (2009) ‘Moral responsibility for environmental problems – individual or institutional?’ Journal of Agricultural and Environmental Ethics, 22 (2): 109–124.

O’Brien, K, Eriksen, S., Sygna, L. and Næss, L.O. (2006) ‘Questioning complacency: climate change impacts, vulnerability, and adaptation in Norway’, Ambio, 35 (2): 50–56.

O’Brien, K., St. Clair, A.L., and Kristoffersen, B. (2010) Climate Change, Ethics and Human Security, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Schipper, L, and Burton, I. (2009) The Earthscan Reader on Adaptation to Climate Change, London: Earthscan.

Singer, P. (1979) Practical Ethics, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Steffen, W. (2009) Climate Change 2009: Faster Change and More Serious Risks, Canberra: Commonwealth of Australia.

Stern, N. H. (2007) Stern Review on the Economics of Climate Change, London: Cambridge University Press.

Vanderheiden, S. (2008) Atmospheric Justice: A Political Theory of Climate Change, Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Weber, E. (2006) ‘Experience-based and description-based perceptions of long-term risk: why global warming does not scare us (yet)’, Climatic Change, 77: 103–120.

Wolf, J. (2010) ‘Ecological citizenship as public engagement with climate change’, in L. Whitmarsh, S.J. O’Neill and I. Lorenzoni (eds) Public Engagement with Climate Change – Behaviour Change and Communication, London, Earthscan: 120–137.

Young, I. M. (2006) ‘Responsibility and global justice: A social connection model’, Philosophy and Social Policy, 23: 102–130.

..................Content has been hidden....................

You can't read the all page of ebook, please click here login for view all page.
Reset
18.217.110.145